User:Phlsph7/Value theory - Value
Value
[edit]Value is the worth, usefulness, or merit of something.[a] Many evaluative terms are employed to talk about value, including good, best, great, and excellent as well as their negative counterparts, like bad and terrible.[3] Some value terms, like good and bad, are pure evaluations in that they only express the value of something without any additional descriptive content. They are known as thin evaluative concepts. Thick evaluative concepts, like courageous and cruel, provide more information by expressing other qualities besides the evaluation, such as character traits.[4] Values are often understood as degrees that cover positive and negative magnitudes corresponding to good and bad. The terms better and worse are used to compare degrees, but it is controversial whether this is possible in all cases.[5]
Evaluative terms are sometimes distinguished from normative or deontic terms. Normative terms, like right, wrong, and obligation, prescribe actions or other states by expressing what ought to be done or what is required.[6] Evaluative terms have a wider scope because they are not limited to what people can control or are responsible for. For example, involuntary events like digestion and earthquakes can have a positive or negative value even if they are not right or wrong in a strict sense.[7] Despite the distinction, evaluative and normative concepts are closely related. For example, the value of the consequences of an action may affect whether this action is right or wrong.[8]
Value theorists distinguish various types or categories of values. The different classifications overlap and are based on considerations like the source, beneficiary, and function of the value.[9]
Intrinsic and instrumental
[edit]A thing has intrinsic or final value if it is good in itself or good for its own sake. This means that it is good independent of external factors or outcomes. A thing has extrinsic or instrumental value if it is useful or leads to other good things. In other words, it is a means to bring about a desired end. For example, tools like microwaves or money have instrumental value thanks to the useful functions they perform.[10] In some cases, the thing produced this way has itself instrumental value, like when using money to buy a microwave. This can result in a chain of instrumentally valuable things in which each link gets its value by causing the following link. Intrinsically valuable things stand at the endpoint of these chains and ground the value of all the links that come before them.[11]
One way to distinguish between intrinsic and instrumental value relies on a thought experiment that imagines the valuable thing in isolation from everything else. In such a situation, purely instrumentally valuable things lose their value since they serve no purpose while purely intrinsically valuable things remain valuable.[12] According to a common view, pleasure is one of the sources of intrinsic value. Other suggested sources include life, health, beauty, freedom, and knowledge.[13]
Intrinsic and instrumental value are not exclusive categories. As a result, a thing can have both intrinsic and instrumental value if it is both good in itself while also leading to other good things.[14] In a similar sense, a thing can have different instrumental values at the same time, both positive and negative ones. This is the case if some of its consequences are good while others are bad. The total instrumental value of a thing is the value balance of all its consequences.[15]
Because instrumental value depends on other values, it is an open question whether it should be understood as a value in a strict sense. For example, the overall value of a chain of causes leading to an intrinsically valuable thing remains the same if instrumentally valuable links are added or removed without affecting the intrinsically valuable thing. The observation that the overall value does not change is sometimes used as an argument that the things added or removed do not have value.[16]
Traditionally, value theorists have used the terms intrinsic value and final value interchangably, just like the terms extrinsic value and instrumental value. This practice has been questioned in the 20th century based on the idea that they are similar but not identical concepts. According to this view, a thing has intrinsic value if the source of its value is an intrinsic property, meaning that the value does not depend on how the thing is related to other objects. Extrinsic value, by contrast, depends on external relations. This view sees instrumental value as one type of extrinsic value based on causal relations. At the same time, it allows that there are other types of non-instrumental extrinsic value. Final value is understood as what is valued for its own sake, independent of whether intrinsic or extrinsic properties are responsible.[17][b]
Absolute and relative
[edit]Another distinction relies on the contrast between absolute and relative value. Absolute value, also called value simpliciter, is a form of unconditional value. A thing has relative value if its value is limited to certain considerations or viewpoints.[19]
One form of relative value is restricted to the type of an entity, expressed in sentences like "That is a good knife" or "Jack is a good thief". This form is known as attributive goodness since the word "good" modifies the meaning of another term. To be attributively good as a certain type means to possess certain qualities characteristic of that type. For example, a good knife is sharp and a good thief has the skill of stealing without getting caught. Attributive goodness contrasts with predicative goodness. The sentence "Pleasure is good" is an example since the word good is used as a predicate to talk about the unqualified value of pleasure.[20] Attributive and predicative goodness can accompany each other, but this is not always the case. For instance, being a good thief is not necessarily a good thing.[21]
Another type of relative value restricts goodness to a specific person. Known as personal value,[c] it expresses what benefits a particular person, promotes their welfare, or is in their interest. For example, a poem written by a child may have personal value for the parents even if the poem lacks value for others. Impersonal value, by contrast, is good in general without restriction to any specific person or viewpoint.[23] Some philosophers, like G. E. Moore, reject the existence of personal values, holding that all values are impersonal. Others have proposed theories about the relation between personal and impersonal value. The agglomerative theory says that impersonal value is nothing but the sum of all personal values. Another view understands impersonal value as a specific type of personal value taken from the perspective of the universe as a whole.[24]
Agent-relative value is sometimes contrasted with personal value as another person-specific limitation of the evaluative outlook. Agent-relative values affect moral considerations about what a person is responsible for or guilty of. For example, if Mei promises to pick Pedro up from the airport then an agent-relative value obligates Mei to drive to the airport. This obligation is in place even if it does not benefit Mei, in which case there is an agent-relative value without a personal value. In consequentialism,[d] agent-relative values are often discussed in relation to ethical dilemmas. One dilemma revolves around the question of whether an individual should murder an innocent person if this prevents the murder of two innocent people by a different perpetrator. The agent-neutral perspective tends to affirm this idea since one murder is preferable to two. The agent-relative perspective tends to reject this conclusion, arguing that the initial murder should be avoided since it negatively impacts the agent-relative value of the individual.[26]
Traditionally, most value theorists see absolute value as the main topic of value theory and focus their attention on this type. Nonetheless, some philosophers, like Peter Geach and Philippa Foot, have argued that the concept of absolute value by itself is meaningless and should be understood as one form of relative value.[27]
Other distinctions
[edit]Other classifications of values have been proposed without a widely accepted main classification.[28] Some focus on the types of entities that have value. They include distinct categories for entities like things, the environment, individuals, groups, and society. Another subdivision pays attention to the type of benefit involved and encompasses material, economic, moral, social, political, aesthetic, and religious values. Classifications by the beneficiary of the value distinguish between self- and other-oriented values.[29]
A historically influential approach identifies three spheres of value: truth, goodness, and beauty.[e] For example, the neo-Kantian philosopher Wilhelm Windelband characterizes them as the highest goals of consciousness, with thought aiming at truth, will aiming at goodness, and emotion aiming at beauty. A similar view, proposed by the Chinese philosopher Zhang Dainian, says that the value of truth belongs to knowledge, the value of goodness belongs to behavior, and the value of beauty belongs to art.[31] This three-fold distinction also plays a central role in the philosophies of Franz Brentano and Jürgen Habermas.[32] Other suggested types of values include objective, subjective, potential, actual, contingent, necessary, inherent, and constitutive values.[33]
References
[edit]Notes
[edit]- ^ The term value has other meanings as well, such as the value of a mathematical variable expressing the information or quantity that this variable carries.[1] Value theory is only interested in the evaluative sense of the term about being good or bad in a certain respect.[2]
- ^ In the social sciences, some works rely on the concept of relational value to understand the value of the relationship between humans and nature. According to this view, relational value is a unique type of value that is neither intrinsic nor instrumental.[18]
- ^ Prudential value is a closely related concepts signifying what is good for a person.[22]
- ^ Consequentialism is a theory in normative ethics. It says that an act is right if it leads to the best consequences.[25]
- ^ In scholastic philosophy, they are known as transcendentals and considered fundamental aspects of being.[30]
Citations
[edit]- ^ HarperCollins 2022
- ^ Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
- ^
- Orsi 2015, p. 1
- Rescher 1969, p. 1
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 2–3
- Hirose & Olson 2015, pp. 3
- ^
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.2 Good, Better, Bad, § 2.3 Incommensurability/Incomparability
- Orsi 2015, pp. 122–123
- Tappolet 2015, p. 82
- ^
- Orsi 2015, p. 8–9
- Schroeder 2021, § 3. Relation to the Deontic
- ^ Hurka 2006, pp. 357–358
- ^
- Orsi 2015, p. 8–9
- Schroeder 2021, § 3. Relation to the Deontic
- Hurka 2006, pp. 357–358
- ^
- Li 2013, p. 70
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.1 Varieties of Goodness
- Orsi 2015, p. 22–23
- Rescher 1969, pp. 13–14, 18
- ^
- Hurka 2006a, pp. 719–720
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 29–30
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, Lead section
- ^
- Hurka 2006a, pp. 719–720
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- ^
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 2. What Is Intrinsic Value?
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 30–31
- ^
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 1. What Has Intrinsic Value?
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- ^
- Schellekens 2010, p. 38
- Vilkka 2021, p. 32
- ^
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- Zimmerman 2001, p. 253
- ^
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- Zimmerman 2001, p. 252
- ^
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1 Intrinsic Value
- Zimmerman & Bradley 2019, § 3. Is There Such a Thing As Intrinsic Value At All?, § 6. What Is Extrinsic Value?
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 29–30
- ^
- Chan, Gould & Pascual 2018, pp. A1–A2
- Jax 2023, p. 59–60
- Gupta 2024, p. 11
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 45–46
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 3–4
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
- Zimmerman 2015, pp. 13–14
- ^ Silverstein 2016, p. 227
- ^ Tiberius 2015, p. [ttps://books.google.com/books?id=uvzVBgAAQBAJ&pg=PA158 158]
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 63–64
- Schroeder 2021, § 1. Basic Questions
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2011, pp. 1–2
- ^
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.1.1 Good Simpliciter and Good For
- Orsi 2015, pp. 63–65
- ^
- Sinnott-Armstrong 2023, Lead section
- Haines, Lead section
- Hooker 2023, § 1. Utilitarianism
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 73–74
- Schroeder 2021, § 3.3 Agent-Relative Value?
- Cullity 2015, pp. 96–97
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 45–46, 61
- Schroeder 2021, § 1.1.2 Attributive Good
- ^ Rescher 1969, pp. 13–14
- ^
- Rescher 1969, pp. 15–16, 18
- Pradhan 2024, p. 142
- Hartman 2011, p. 306
- ^ De Haan 2020, p. 302
- ^
- Li 2013, pp. 80–81
- Ollig 1998, Lead section
- Martin 2016, pp. 3–5, 42–43
- ^
- Martin 2016, pp. 4–5
- Kriegel 2018, pp. 96–97, 149, 253, 288
- ^
- Orsi 2015, pp. 44
- Bahm 1993, p. 60–63
- Schroeder 2021, § 2.1.1 What is Intrinsic Value?
- Rønnow-Rasmussen 2015, pp. 39–40
Sources
[edit]- Gupta, Abhik (2024). Many Layers of Ecocentrism: Revering Life, Revering the Earth. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-040-03034-9.
- Jax, Kurt (2023). Conservation Concepts: Rethinking Human–Nature Relationships. Taylor & Francis. ISBN 978-1-000-99354-7.
- Chan, Kai MA; Gould, Rachelle K; Pascual, Unai (2018). "Editorial overview: Relational values: what are they, and what's the fuss about?". Current Opinion in Environmental Sustainability. 35. doi:10.1016/j.cosust.2018.11.003.
- Kriegel, Uriah (2018). Brentano's Philosophical System: Mind, Being, Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-879148-5.
- Hooker, Brad (2023). "Rule Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on February 1, 2024. Retrieved 29 December 2023.
- Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter (2023). "Consequentialism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Archived from the original on June 18, 2023. Retrieved 28 December 2023.
- Haines, William. "Consequentialism and Utilitarianism". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Archived from the original on December 24, 2023. Retrieved 28 December 2023.
- Hartman, Robert S. (2011). The Structure of Value: Foundations of Scientific Axiology. Wipf and Stock Publishers. ISBN 978-1-7252-3067-5.
- Pradhan, Ramesh Chandra (2024). Ethics, Self and the World: Exploring Metaphysical Foundations in Moral Philosophy. Springer Nature Singapore. ISBN 978-981-97-3496-2.
- Tiberius, Valerie (2015). "Prudential Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Martin, John Levi (2016). "The Birth of the True, The Good, and The Beautiful: Toward an Investigation of the Structures of Social Thought". Current Perspectives in Social Theory. 35: 3–56. doi:10.1108/S0278-120420160000035001.
- Ollig, Hans-Ludwig (1998). "Neo-Kantianism". Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Routledge. doi:10.4324/9780415249126-DC055-1.
- De Haan, Daniel D. (2020). "Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas". In Ramos, Daniel D. De Haan; Beauty and Aesthetic Perception in Thomas Aquinas (ed.). Beauty and the Good: Recovering the Classical Tradition from Plato to Duns Scotus. CUA Press. ISBN 978-0-8132-3353-6.
{{cite book}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: editors list (link) - Cullity, Garrett (2015). "Neutral and Relative Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni (2011). Personal Value. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-960378-7.
- Silverstein, Matthew (2016). "Teleology and Normativity". In Shafer-Landau, Russ (ed.). Oxford Studies in Metaethics 11. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-878464-7.
- Zimmerman, Michael J. (2015). "Value and Normativity". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Vilkka, Leena (2021). The Intrinsic Value of Nature. Brill. ISBN 978-90-04-49510-4.
- Schellekens, Elisabeth (2010). Aesthetics and Morality. Bloomsbury Publishing. ISBN 978-1-4411-2298-8.
- Zimmerman, Michael J.; Bradley, Ben (2019). "Intrinsic vs. Extrinsic Value". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 29 August 2024.
- Rønnow-Rasmussen, Toni (2015). "Intrinsic and Extrinsic Value". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- Hurka, Thomas (2006a). "Intrinsic Value". In Borchert, Donald M. (ed.). Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Vol. 4 (2 ed.). Macmillan. ISBN 978-0-02-866072-1.
- Zimmerman, Michael J. (2001). The Nature of Intrinsic Value. Rowman & Littlefield. ISBN 978-0-7425-1263-4.
- Tappolet, Christine (2015). "Values and Emotions". In Hirose, Iwao; Olson, Jonas (eds.). The Oxford Handbook of Value Theory. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-022143-0.
- HarperCollins (2022). "Value". The American Heritage Dictionary entry. HarperCollins. Retrieved 28 August 2024.
- Rescher, Nicholas (1969). Introduction to Value Theory. Prentice-Hall. ISBN 978-0-13-500751-8.