User:Phlsph7/Rule of inference - Systems of logic
Systems of logic
[edit]Propositional logic
[edit]Propositional logic examines the inferential patterns of simple and compound propositions. It uses letters, such as and , to represent simple propositions. Compound propositions are formed by modifying or combining simple propositions with logical operators, such as (not), (and), (or), and (if ... then ...). For example, if stands for the statement "it is raining" and stands for the statement "the streets are wet", then expresses "it is not raining" and expresses "if it is raining then the streets are wet". These logical operators are truth-functional, meaning that the truth value of a compound proposition depends only on the truth values of the simple propositions composing it. For instance, the compound proposition is only true if both and are true; in all other cases, it is false. Propositional logic is not concerned with the concrete meaning of propositions other than their truth values.[1] Key rules of inference in propositional logic are modus ponens, modus tollens, hypothetical syllogism, and disjunctive syllogism. Further rules include conjunction introduction, disjunction introduction, constructive dilemma, destructive dilemma, double negation elimination, and De Morgan's laws.[2]
Rule of inference | Form | Example |
---|---|---|
Modus ponens | ||
Modus tollens | ||
Hypothetical syllogism | ||
Disjunctive syllogism |
First-order logic
[edit]Classical first-order logic also employs the logical operators from propositional logic but includes additional devices to articulate the internal structure of propositions. Basic propositions in first-order logic consist of a predicate, symbolized with uppercase letters like and , which is applied to singular terms, symbolized with lowercase letters like and . For example, if stands for "Aristotle" and stands for "is a philosopher", the formula means that "Aristotle is a philosopher". Another innovation of first-order logic is the use of the quantifiers and , which express that a predicate applies to some or all individuals. For instance, the formula expresses that philosophers exist while expresses that everyone is a philosopher. The rules of inference from propositional logic are also valid in first-order logic.[4] Additionally, first-order logic introduces new rules of inference that govern the role of singular terms, predicates, and quantifiers in arguments. Key rules of inference are universal instantiation and existential generalization. Other rules of inference include universal generalization and existential instantiation.[5]
Rule of inference | Form | Example |
---|---|---|
Universal instantiation | [a] | |
Existential generalization |
Modal logics
[edit]Modal logics are formal systems that extend propositional logic and first-order logic with additional logical operators. Alethic modal logic introduces the operator to express that something is possible and the operator to express that something is necessary. For example, if the means that "Parvati works", then means that "It is possible that Parvati works" while means that "It is necessary that Parvati works". These two operators are related by a rule of replacement stating that is equivalent to . In other words: if something is necessarily true then it is not possible that it is not true. Further rules of inference include the necessitation rule, which asserts that a statement is necessarily true if it is provable in a formal system without any additional premises, and the distribution axiom, which allows one to derive from . These rules of inference belong to system K, a weak form of modal logic with only the most basic rules of inference. Many formal systems of alethic modal logic include additional rules of inference, such as system T, which allows one to deduce from .[7]
Non-alethic systems of modal logic introduce operators that behave like and in alethic modal logic, following similar rules of inference but with different meanings. Deontic logic is one type of non-alethic logic. It uses the operator to express that an action is permitted and the operator to express that an action is required, where behaves similarly to and behaves similarly to . For instance, the rule of replacement in alethic modal logic asserting that is equivalent to also applies to deontic logic. As a result, one can deduce from (e.g. Quinn has an obligation to help) that (e.g. Quinn is not permitted not to help).[8] Other systems of modal logic include temporal modal logic, which has operators for what is always or sometimes the case, as well as doxastic and epistemic modal logics, which have operators for what people believe and know.[9]
Others
[edit]Many other systems of logic have been proposed. One of the earliest systems is Aristotelian logic, according to which each statement is made up of two terms, a subject and a predicate, connected by a copula. For example, the statement "all humans are mortal" has the subject "all humans", the predicate "mortal", and the copula "is". All rules of inference in Aristotelian logic have the form of syllogisms, which consist of two premises and a conclusion. For instance, the Barbara rule of inference describes the validity of arguments of the form "All men are mortal. All Greeks are men. Therefore, all Greeks are mortal."[10]
Second-order logic extends first-order logic by allowing quantifiers to apply to predicates in addition to singular terms. For example, to express that the individuals Adam () and Bianca () share a property, one can use the formula .[11] Second-order logic also comes with new rules of inference.[b] For instance, one can infer (Adam is a philosopher) from (every property applies to Adam).[13]
Intuitionistic logic is a non-classical variant of propositional and first-order logic. It shares with them many rules of inference, such as modus ponens, but excludes certain rules. For example, in classical logic, one can infer from using the rule of double negation elimination. However, in intuitionistic logic, this inference is invalid. As a result, every theorem that can be deduced in intuitionistic logic can also be deduced in classical logic, but some theorems provable in classical logic cannot be proven in intuitionistic logic.[14]
Paraconsistent logics revise classical logic to allow the existence of contradictions. In logic, a contradiction happens if the same proposition is both affirmed and denied, meaning that a formal system contains both and as theorems. Classical logic prohibits contradictions because classical rules of inference lead to the principle of explosion, an admissible rule of inference that makes it possible to infer from the premises and . Since is unrelated to , any arbitrary statement can be deduced from a contradiction, making the affected systems useless for deciding what is true and false.[15] Paraconsistent logics solve this problem by modifying the rules of inference in such a way that the principle of explosion is not an admissible rule of inference. As a result, it is possible to reason about inconsistent information without deriving absurd conclusions.[16]
Many-valued logics modify classical logic by introducing additional truth values. In classical logic, a proposition is either true or false with nothing inbetween. In many-valued logics, some propositions are neither true nor false. Kleene logic, for example, is a three-valued logic that introduces the additional truth value undefined to describe situations where information is incomplete or uncertain.[17] Many-valued logics have adjusted rules of inference to accommodate the additional truth values. For instance, the classical rule of replacement stating that is equivalent to is invalid in many three-valued systems.[18]
References
[edit]Notes
[edit]- ^ This example assumes that refers to an individual in the domain of discourse.
- ^ An important difference between first-order and second-order logic is that second-order logic is incomplete, meaning that it is not possible to provide a finite set of rules of inference with which every theorem can be deduced.[12]
Citations
[edit]- ^
- Klement, Lead section, § 1. Introduction, § 3. The Language of Propositional Logic
- Sider 2010, pp. 30–35
- ^
- Hurley 2016, p. 303
- Copi, Cohen & Flage 2016, pp. 247
- Klement, § Deduction: Rules of Inference and Replacement
- ^
- Hurley 2016, p. 303
- Copi, Cohen & Flage 2016, pp. 247
- ^
- Shapiro & Kouri Kissel 2024, Lead section, § 2. Language
- Sider 2010, pp. 115–118
- Cook 2009, pp. 119–120
- ^
- Hurley 2016, pp. 374–377
- Shapiro & Kouri Kissel 2024, § 3. Deduction
- ^
- Hurley 2016, pp. 374–377
- Shapiro & Kouri Kissel 2024, § 3. Deduction
- ^
- Garson 2024, Lead section, § 2. Modal Logics
- Sider 2010, pp. 171–176, 286–287
- ^ Garson 2024, § 3. Deontic Logics
- ^
- Garson 2024, § 1. What is Modal Logic?, § 4. Temporal Logics
- Sider 2010, pp. 234–242
- ^
- Smith 2022, Lead section, § 3. The Subject of Logic: “Syllogisms”
- Groarke, Lead section, § 3. From Words into Propositions, § 4. Kinds of Propositions, § 9. The Syllogism
- ^ Väänänen 2024, Lead section, § 1. Introduction
- ^
- Väänänen 2024, § 1. Introduction
- Grandy 1979, p. 122
- Linnebo 2014, p. 123
- ^ Pollard 2015, p. 98
- ^
- Moschovakis 2024, Lead section, § 1. Rejection of Tertium Non Datur
- Sider 2010, pp. 110–114, 264–265
- Kleene 2000, p. 81
- ^
- Shapiro & Kouri Kissel 2024, § 3. Deduction
- Sider 2010, pp. 102–104
- Priest, Tanaka & Weber 2025, Lead section
- ^
- Weber, Lead section, § 2. Logical Background
- Sider 2010, pp. 102–104
- Priest, Tanaka & Weber 2025, Lead section
- ^
- Sider 2010, pp. 93–94, 98–100
- Gottwald 2022, Lead section, § 3.4 Three-valued systems
- ^
- Egré & Rott 2021, § 2. Three-Valued Conditionals
- Gottwald 2022, Lead section, § 2. Proof Theory
Sources
[edit]- Garson, James (2024). "Modal Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 22 March 2025.
- Pollard, Stephen (2015). Philosophical Introduction to Set Theory. Courier Dover Publications. ISBN 978-0-486-80582-5.
- Grandy, R. E. (1979). Advanced Logic for Applications. D. Reidel Publishing Company. ISBN 978-90-277-1034-5.
- Linnebo, Øystein (2014). "Higher-Order Logic". In Horsten, Leon; Pettigrew, Richard (eds.). The Bloomsbury Companion to Philosophical Logic. Bloomsbury Publishing. pp. 105–127. ISBN 978-1-4725-2829-2.
- Väänänen, Jouko (2024). "Second-order and Higher-order Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 March 2025.
- Weber, Zach. "Paraconsistent Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 23 March 2025.
- Moschovakis, Joan (2024). "Intuitionistic Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 23 March 2025.
- Egré, Paul; Rott, Hans (2021). "The Logic of Conditionals". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 March 2025.
- Klement, Kevin C. "Propositional Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 24 March 2025.
- Shapiro, Stewart; Kouri Kissel, Teresa (2024). "Classical Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University.
- Priest, Graham; Tanaka, Koji; Weber, Zach (2025). "Paraconsistent Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 March 2025.
- Gottwald, Siegfried (2022). "Many-Valued Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 March 2025.
- Smith, Robin (2022). "Aristotle's Logic". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Metaphysics Research Lab, Stanford University. Retrieved 24 March 2025.
- Groarke, Louis F. "Aristotle: Logic". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 24 March 2025.
- Kleene, S. C. (2000). "II. Various Notions of Realizability". In Beklemishev, Lev D. (ed.). The Foundations of Intuitionistic Mathematics. Elsevier. ISBN 978-0-08-095759-3.