User:Mnusom/Open-question argument
![]() | This is the sandbox page where you will draft your initial Wikipedia contribution.
If you're starting a new article, you can develop it here until it's ready to go live. If you're working on improvements to an existing article, copy only one section at a time of the article to this sandbox to work on, and be sure to use an edit summary linking to the article you copied from. Do not copy over the entire article. You can find additional instructions here. Remember to save your work regularly using the "Publish page" button. (It just means 'save'; it will still be in the sandbox.) You can add bold formatting to your additions to differentiate them from existing content. |
Article Draft
[edit]The open-question argument is a philosophical argument put forward by British philosopher G. E. Moore in §13 of Principia Ethica (1903), to refute the equating of the property of goodness with some non-moral property, X, whether natural (e.g. pleasure) or supernatural (e.g. God's command). That is, Moore's argument attempts to show that no moral property is identical to a natural property. Where a moral property is a term used to describe the moral value of things and a natural property is something that exists in the natural world and can be observed, measured, or quantified, e.g., pleasure, pain, and desire. The argument takes the form of a syllogism modus tollens:
- Premise 1: If X is (analytically equivalent to) good, then the question "Is it true that X is good?" is meaningless.
- Premise 2: The question "Is it true that X is good?" is not meaningless (i.e. it is an open question).
- Conclusion: X is not (analytically equivalent to) good.
The type of question Moore refers to in this argument is an identity question, "Is it true that X is Y?" Such a question is an open question if a conceptually competent speaker can question this; otherwise it is closed. For example, "I know he is a vegan, but does he eat meat?" would be a closed question since it is by definition a vegan does not eat meet. However, "I know that it is pleasurable, but is it good?" is an open question; the answer cannot be derived from the meaning of the terms alone.
The open-question argument claims that any attempt to identify morality with some set of observable, natural properties will always be liable to an open question, and that if this is true, then moral facts cannot be reduced to natural properties and that therefore Ethical naturalism is false. Put another way, Moore is saying that any attempt to define good in terms of a natural property fails because such definitions can be transformed into closed questions (the subject and predicate being conceptually identical, that is, the two terms mean the same thing); however, all purported naturalistic definitions of good are transformable into open questions, for it can still be questioned whether good is the same thing as pleasure, etc. Shortly before (in section §11), Moore had said if good is defined as pleasure, or any other natural property, "good" may be substituted for "pleasure", or that other property, anywhere where it occurs. However, "pleasure is good" is a meaningful, informative statement; but "good is good" (after making the substitution) is a uninformative Tautology.
Moore applied the open-question argument to specific naturalist claims of how good can be defined. He scrutinized the attempts to define "good" that the naturalists made in terms of pleasure (Hedonism), evolution (Evolutionary ethics), or Metaphysics. Moore demonstrated how his open-question argument challenged these different naturalist proposals.
Moore presented the open-question argument in two different ways:
1. If a naturalist claim were true, then stating that "Pleasure is good" would be equivalent in stating that "Pleasure is pleasure." However, stating that "Pleasure is good" is meant to express more than just that uninformative tautology.
2. If a naturalist claim were true, then a statement like "x is pleasant but x is not good" would be self-contradictory. If it were known that x is pleasant, the question of whether it is good would be closed, but Moore argues that the question remains open.
These nuances in Moore's presentation of the argument expose the limitations of naturalist proposals and reveal the complexities in his approach to the open-question argument.[1]
Objections and rejoinders[edit]
[edit]Begging the question[edit]
[edit]The idea that Moore begs the question (i.e. assumes the conclusion in a premise) was first raised by William Frankena. Since analytic equivalency, for two objects X and Y, logically results in the question "Is it true that X is Y?" being meaningless (by Moore's own argument), to say that the question is meaningless is to concede analytic equivalency. Thus Moore begs the question in the second premise. He assumes that the question is a meaningful one (i.e. that it is an open question). This begs the question and the open-question argument thus fails.
In response to this, the open-question argument can be reformulated. The Darwall-Gibbard-Railton reformulation argues for the impossibility of equating a moral property with a non-moral one using the internalist theory of motivation. Goodness, on this account, is the property which ideally gives rise to certain internal states (motivations, sentiments, desires to act), but is not, itself, equivalent to those states.
The internalist, or Humean, theory of motivation (belief–desire–intention model) is the view that if one has a reason to act, one must have some desire which would be fulfilled by that act, compared to the externalist theory of motivation, which holds that we may have reasons to act absent any accompanying desire. According to internalism, moral motivation comes from the (global) benefit or utility of moral sentiments or actions. On the other hand, externalism holds that moral properties give us reasons for acting independent of desire or utility. If internalism is true, then the OQA may avoid begging the question against the naturalist by claiming that the moral properties and the motivations to act belong to different categories, and therefore, necessarily are not analytically equivalent. That is, it remains an open question whether the properties which do give rise to certain sentiments ought to guide our actions in that way. To argue for the special motivational effects of moral beliefs is to commit the fallacy of special pleading.
Meaningful analysis[edit]
[edit]The main assumption within the open-question argument can be found within premise 1. It is assumed that analytic equivalency will result in meaningless analysis. Thus, if we understand Concept C, and Concept C* can be analysed in terms of Concept C, then we should grasp concept C* by virtue of our understanding of Concept C. Yet it is obvious that such understanding of Concept C* only comes about through the analysis proper. Mathematics would be the prime example: mathematics is tautological and its claims are true by definition, yet we can develop new mathematical conceptions and theorems.
In addition to mathematics, there are other domains where analytic equivalency does not necessarily result in meaningless analysis. This frequently occurs with scientific discoveries. These discoveries often uncover relationships between things in our natural world that are fundamentally analytical, yet they still provide valuable information. An example of this is the discovery that temperature is a measure of the average kinetic energy of particles in a substance. This relationship may seem analytically equivalent, however, understanding this connection remarkably improved our knowledge of thermodynamics and opened the way for future scientific advancements.[2] This further shows that even in situations where there is analytic equivalency, there still exists the ability to derive valuable information and meaning from it. Thus, X (i.e. some non-moral property) might well be analytically equivalent to the good, and still the question of "Is X good?" can be meaningful. Ergo premise 1 does not hold and the argument falls.
Main article: Sense and reference
Sense and reference are two different aspects of some terms' meanings. A term's reference is the object to which the term refers, while the term's sense is the way that the term refers to that object.
There is a difference between the sense of a term and its reference (i.e. the object itself). Thus, we can understand a claim like "goodness is identical with pleasure" as an a posteriori identity claim similar to "Water is H2O". The question "This is H2O but is it water?" is intelligible and so, in that limited sense, whether or not water is H2O is an open question; note that this does not address the issue of significance. But that does not lead us to conclude that water is not H2O. "Water is H2O" is an identity claim that is known to be true a posteriori (i.e., it was discovered via empirical investigation). Another example is "redness" being identical to certain phenomena of electromagnetism. This is discovered by empirical investigation. Similarly, many moral naturalists argue that "rightness" can be discovered as an a posteriori truth, by investigating the different claims, like that of pleasure being the good, or of duty being the good.
This is done by invoking rightness and wrongness to explain certain empirical phenomena, and then discovering a posteriori whether maximizing utility occupies the relevant explanatory role. For example, they argue that since right actions contingently have certain effects e.g. being causally responsible for a tendency towards social stability—so it follows we can fix the term "right" refer to the empirical description "the property of acts, whatever it is, that is causally responsible for their tendency towards social stability." With this description for "right," we can then investigate which acts accomplish this: e.g. those actions that maximize utility. We can then conclude that we have learned that "right" refers to "maximizing utility" through a posteriori means.
The Frege sense–reference distinction can be understood in layman's terms by using the analogy of the Masked Man. A citizen living on the frontiers of the Wild West is told by the sheriff that his brother is the Masked Man who has recently been robbing banks. The citizen protests that he understands who his brother is, and who the Masked Man is supposed to be, and can meaningfully ask, "Is my brother the Masked Man?" Obviously, analytic equivalency is of no relevance here. The matter is an empirical one, which the citizen must investigate a posteriori. The absurdity of dismissing the claim as such is apparent.
Notes and references[edit]
[edit]- ^ .
- ^ , p. 230.
- ^ .
- ^ Copp 2001.
- ^ Copp 2001.
- ^ Copp 2001.
- ^ , p. 28.
- ^ LaFollette 2000.
- ^ Fyfe, A. : Desire Utilitarianism,
Solutions to the Paradox of Analysis
[edit]The Linguistic Solution
[edit]The linguistic solution proposed by Max Black states that a in fact can equal b and be informative because the information you gain from a definition is which expressions pick out the same concept [3]. For example, saying that someone is a bachelor is equivalent to saying that the person can be equally well described by the phrase "an unmarried man". Even though the two expressions mean the same thing, what we have learned is that the combination of letters that make up the word "bachelor" picks out the same concept as the particular combination of spaces and letters as "an unmarried man". Similarly consider the math example of 3x7=21 and 1x21=21. It is certainly true that "3x7" and "1x21" pick out the same number and as a result, would not say that no information was gained by saying 3x7=1x21. We would not say this because we have learned that the expression "3x7" picks out the same number as the expression "1x21" [4]. Overall, this solution aims to say that we do gain knowledge from definitions but that knowledge is linguistic.
The "Explicit Knowledge" Solution
[edit]The "explicit knowledge" solution comes from philosophers Mark Balaguer and Terry Horgan. The goal of the "explicit knowledge" solution is to say that a good analysis will take someone from being able to implicity apply the concept correctly, to being able to explicitly explain and know why their application is correct [5].The information we gain then, is how to make explicit what we before only knew implicitly. Take a circle for example. Most children and adults if you ask them to pick which things are circles would be able to. However, if you ask them what the definition of a circle is, most people will struggle. The definition of a circle is "a plane figure bounded by one curved line, and such that all straight lines drawn from a certain point within it to the bounding line, are equal. The bounding line is called its circumference and the point, its centre." [6] To someone who knows implicitly what a circle is, upon hearing this definition will say, "of course" or "that makes sense" because they had the implicit knowledge. All the definition, or analysis, did, was to make explicit what the children and adults already implicitly knew about the concept of "circle". Therefore, the solution says that an analysis is informative because it creates explicit knowledge to those who only had implicit knowledge of the concept prior to knowing the definition[7].
- ^ Hurka, Thomas (2005-01-26). "Moore's Moral Philosophy".
{{cite journal}}
: Cite journal requires|journal=
(help) - ^ Middleton, W. E. Knowles (1966). A History of the Thermometer and Its Use in Meteorology. Johns Hopkins University Press. ISBN 978-0-8018-0462-5.
- ^ Black, Max (1944), The "Paradox of Analysis", Oxford University Press.
- ^ Black, Max (1944), The "Paradox of Analysis", Oxford University Press
- ^ Balaguer, Horgan, Mark,Terry (2016), A Solution to the Paradox of Analysis, Oxford University Press
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link). - ^ Euclid (1883), Books. I,II, Oxford University Press.
- ^ Balaguer, Horgan, Mark,Terry (2016), Analysis, vol. 76 no.1, Oxford University Press, pp. 3–7
{{citation}}
: CS1 maint: multiple names: authors list (link).