Argumentation scheme
This article, Argumentation scheme, has recently been created via the Articles for creation process. Please check to see if the reviewer has accidentally left this template after accepting the draft and take appropriate action as necessary.
Reviewer tools: Inform author |
This article, Argumentation scheme, has recently been created via the Articles for creation process. Please check to see if the reviewer has accidentally left this template after accepting the draft and take appropriate action as necessary.
Reviewer tools: Inform author |
Comment: It's still not clear how this is different from argumentation theory or rhetoric in general. AngusWOOF (bark • sniff) 08:15, 1 May 2020 (UTC)
Comment: Some of the examples do not need to be such detail as they already have articles. Argument from authority, Argument from ignorance, Syllogism. AngusWOOF (bark • sniff) 08:14, 1 May 2020 (UTC)
Comment: I just discovered this draft, written by Waleedmebane and Fabriziomacagno, after I started thinking that it could be useful to have an article on this subject. I have completely revised the first two paragraphs with the aim of making them clearer, and I made a few other minor edits throughout. AngusWOOF suggested redirecting to Argumentation theory, but the reason given wasn't correct. That article doesn't really say anything about argumentation schemes, and merging all of this material into that article would be undue weight. If you look at some of the other long articles about obscure areas of logic, you can see that an article on argumentation schemes is not out of place on Wikipedia, even if the subject is a little technical. I would also like to see a simple list of argumentation schemes in this article. I will have to figure out how to resubmit this article after it has been sufficiently cleaned up. Biogeographist (talk) 19:15, 27 April 2020 (UTC)
Comment: The first sentence should be an in-your-face explanation of what the topic is. You've got this sentence: Template:Tq is only for quoting in talk and project pages. Do not use it in actual articles. burried somewhere deep in the second paragraph. It's the first place you actually say what the topic is, i.e. Argumentation schemes are.... The next problem is that the sentence is so long and complicated, by the time you get to the end of it, you've forgotten where you started. Pretend you've just met somebody who knows nothing about the topic. You've got 30 seconds to explain to them what it is. Write a sentence that lets you do that. Make it the first sentence in the article. -- RoySmith (talk) 01:53, 10 October 2019 (UTC)
Comment: This should redirect to either Argumentation theory or Douglas N. Walton, the latter of whom called the argumentation theory a scheme as part of his argumentation method. AngusWOOF (bark • sniff) 03:07, 16 July 2019 (UTC)
In argumentation theory, an argumentation scheme or argument scheme is a template that represents a common type of argument used in ordinary conversation. Many different argumentation schemes have been identified. Each one has a name (for example, "argument from effect to cause") and presents a type of connection between premises and a conclusion in an argument, and this connection is expressed as a rule of inference. Argumentation schemes may include inferences based on different types of reasoning: deductive, inductive, abductive, probabilistic, or others.
One argumentation scheme is the scheme called argument from effect to cause, which has the form: "if A occurs, then B will (or might) occur, and in this case B occurred, so in this case A presumably occurred". This scheme may apply in the example where someone argues that presumably there was a fire here since there was smoke here and if there is a fire then there will be smoke—an argument that looks like the formal fallacy of affirming the consequent ("if A is true then B is also true, and B is true, so A must be true"), but in this example the material conditional logical connective ("A implies B") in the formal fallacy does not account for exactly why the semantic relation between premises and conclusion, namely causality ("fire causes smoke") may be reasonable, while not all formally valid conditional premises are reasonable (such as in the valid modus ponens argument "if there is a cat here then there is smoke here, and there is a cat here, so there must be smoke here"). More than one argumentation scheme may apply to the same argument; in this example, the more complex abductive argumentation scheme may also apply.
Overview
Since the beginning of the discipline called rhetoric,[1] the study of the types of argument has been a central issue.[2][3][4] The analysis of types of arguments allows a speaker to find the argument form that is most suitable to a specific subject matter and context—for example, arguments based on authority can be useful in courts of law but not in a classroom discussion; arguments based on analogy are often effective in political discourse, but tend to be problematic in a scientific discussion.
The two interrelated goals of argument recognition and analysis were the core of ancient dialectics, and specifically the branch called topics.[5][6][7] In the 20th century, the ancient interest in types of arguments was revived in several academic disciplines, including education, artificial intelligence, legal philosophy, and discourse analysis.
The study of this ancient subject is mostly carried out today in the field of study called argumentation theory under the name of argumentation schemes.[8][9]
An example of an argumentation scheme is the scheme for argument from position to know given below.[10]
Premise: | a is in a position to know whether A is true or false. |
Assertion premise: | a asserts that A is true ([or] false). |
Conclusion: | a may plausibly be taken to be true ([or] false). |
According to the usual convention in argumentation theory, arguments are given as a list of premises followed by a single conclusion. The premises are the grounds given by the speaker or writer for the hearer or reader to accept the conclusion as true or as provisionally true (regarded as true for now). An argumentation scheme's definition is not itself an argument, but represents the structure of an argument of a certain type. The letters in the scheme, lower case a and upper case A, need to be filled in if an argument is to be created from the scheme. Lower case a would be replaced by the name of a person and upper case A by a proposition, which might be true or false.
Argumentation theorist Douglas N. Walton gives the following example of an argument that fits the argument from position to know scheme: "It looks as if this passer-by knows the streets, and she says that City Hall is over that way; therefore, let's go ahead and accept the conclusion that City Hall is that way."[11]
History
Among contemporary authors, Chaïm Perelman and Lucie Olbrechts-Tyteca may have been the first to write about argumentation schemes, which they called "argumentative schemes".[12] They present a long list of schemes together with explanation and examples in part three of The New Rhetoric. The argumentation schemes in The New Rhetoric are not described in terms of their logical structure, as in more recent scholarship on argumentation schemes; they are given prose descriptions. The structure of the arguments is, nevertheless, considered important by the authors.[13]
Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca also suggest a link between argumentation schemes and the loci (Latin) or topoi (Greek) of classical writers.[14] Both words, literally translated, mean "places" in their respective languages. Loci is a Latin translation of the Greek, topoi, used by Aristotle in his work, Topics, about logical argument and reasoning. Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca explain loci as: "headings under which arguments can be classified".[15] And they write, "They are associated with a concern to help a speaker's inventive efforts and involve the grouping of relevant material, so that it can be easily found again when required."[16] While Aristotle's treatment of topoi is not the same as the modern treatment of argumentation schemes, it is reasonable to consider Aristotle as the first writer in the genre.[17]
The first contemporary writer to treat argumentation schemes in the way they are treated by current scholars and the way they are described in this article may have been Arthur Hastings in his 1963 Ph.D. dissertation.[18]
Forms of inference
The study of argument in the field of argumentation theory since The New Rhetoric and Stephen Toulmin's The Uses of Argument, both first published in 1958, has been characterized by a recognition of the defeasible, non-monotonic nature of most ordinary everyday arguments and reasoning. A defeasible argument is one that can be defeated, and that defeat is achieved when new information is discovered that shows that there was a relevant exception to our argument in the presence of which the conclusion can no longer be accepted. A common example used in textbooks concerns Tweety, a bird that may or may not fly:[19]
- (All) birds can fly;
- Tweety is a bird;
- Therefore, Tweety can fly.
The argument above (with the addition of "All", which is shown in parentheses) has the form of a logical syllogism and is, therefore, valid. If the first two statements, the premises, are true, then the third statement, the conclusion, must also be true. However, if we subsequently learn that Tweety is a penguin or has a broken wing, we can no longer conclude that Tweety can fly. In the context of deductive inference, we would have to conclude that our first premise was simply false. Deductive inference rules are not subject to exception. But there can be defeasible generalizations (inference rules). When we say that birds can fly, we mean that it is generally the case, subject to exceptions. We are justified in making the inference and accepting the conclusion that this particular bird can fly until we find out that an exception applies in this particular case.[20]
In addition to deductive inference and defeasible inference, there is also probabilistic inference. A probabilistic version of the generalization, "birds can fly", might be: "There is a 75% chance that a bird will be found to be able to fly" or "if something is a bird it probably can fly." The probabilistic version is also capable of being defeated, defeasible, but it includes the idea that the uncertainty might be quantifiable according to axioms of probability. (An exact number need not be attached as in the first example.)
In some theories, argumentation schemes are mostly schemes for argumentation with defeasible inference although there could be schemes for specialized areas of discourse using other forms of inference, such as probability in the sciences.[21] For most or all everyday arguments, the schemes are defeasible.
In other theories, the argumentation schemes are deductive or there is an attempt to interpret the schemes in a probabilistic way.[22]
Examples
Argument from expert opinion
Argument from expert opinion can be considered a sub-type of the argument from position to know presented at the beginning of the article. In this case, the person who is in a position to know is an expert who knows about some field.[23]
Major premise: | Source E is an expert in subject domain S containing proposition A. |
Minor premise: | E asserts that proposition A is true (false). |
Conclusion: | A is true (false). |
Critical questions
The schemes of Walton (1996) and Walton, Reed, and Macagno (2008) come with critical questions. Critical questions are questions that could be asked to throw doubt on the argument's support for its conclusion. They are targeted toward key assumptions that, if true, make the argument acceptable. The reason these assumptions are presented in the form of questions is that these schemes are a part of a dialectical theory of argumentation.[24] An argument is dialectical when it is a back and forth of argument and rebuttal or questioning. This can be the case even when there is only one reasoner, presenting arguments, then seeking out new information or sources of doubt, or critically probing their own initial assumptions. Since everyday arguments are typically defeasible, this is an approach to strengthening a case over time, testing each element of the case and discarding those parts that do not stand up to scrutiny.[25] The critical questions for argument from expert opinion, given in Walton, Reed, and Macagno (2008), are shown below.
CQ1: Expertise question: | How credible is E as an expert source? |
CQ2: Field question: | Is E an expert in the field that A is in? |
CQ3: Opinion question: | What did E assert that implies A? |
CQ4: Trustworthiness question: | Is E personally reliable as a source? |
CQ5: Consistency question: | Is A consistent with what other experts assert? |
CQ6: Backup evidence question: | Is E's assertion based on evidence? |
Another version of the scheme argument from expert opinion, given in a textbook by Groarke and Tindale, does not include critical questions. Instead more of the key assumptions are included as additional premises of the argument.
Argument from ignorance
Argument from ignorance can be stated in a very informal way as, "if it were true, I would know it".[26] Walton gives the following example of an argument from ignorance: "The posted train schedule says that train 12 to Amsterdam stops at Haarlem and Amsterdam Central Station. We want to determine whether the train stops at Schipol. We can reason as follows: Since the schedule did not indicate that the train stops at Schipol, we can infer that it does not stop at Schipol."[27] Examples very much like this are well known in computer science discussions about the closed-world assumption for databases.[citation needed] We might suppose that the train operating authority has a policy of maintaining a complete database of all of the stops and of publishing schedules reflecting that. In cases such as that we have a pretty good assurance that our inference is correct even though it is possible for information to be missing from the database or not included in some particular schedule posting.
The scheme and its accompanying critical questions are shown below.[28]
Major premise: | If A were true, then A would be known to be true. |
Minor premise: | It is not the case that A is known to be true. |
Conclusion: | Therefore, A is not true. |
CQ1: | How far along has the search for evidence progressed? |
CQ2: | Which side has the burden of proof in the dialogue as a whole? In other words, what is the ultimate probandum [claim that is to be proved] and who is supposed to prove it? |
CQ3: | How strong does the proof need to be in order for this party to be successful in fulfilling the burden. |
These critical questions, CQ2 and CQ3, especially show the dialectical nature of the theory from which this scheme derives. Two dialectical concerns are considered. It might be the case, as in some legal systems that there is a presumption favoring a certain position—e.g., a presumption of innocence favoring the accused. In that case, the burden of proof is on the accuser, and it would not be proper to argue in the opposite direction: if the accused were innocent I would have known about it; I don't know about it; therefore, the accused is not innocent. Even if it were a proper argument, the standard of proof in such a case (as asked in CQ3) is very high, beyond a reasonable doubt, but the argument from ignorance alone might be very weak. When challenged, additional arguments would be needed to build a sufficiently strong case.
See Practical reason § in argumentation for argumentation schemes for practical reasoning.
Relation to fallacies
Many of the names of argumentation schemes may be familiar to readers because of their history as names of fallacies and because of the history of the teaching of fallacies in critical thinking and informal logic courses. In his groundbreaking work, Fallacies, C. L. Hamblin challenged the idea that the traditional fallacies are always fallacious.[29] Subsequently, Walton described the fallacies as kinds of arguments; they can be used properly and provide support for conclusions, support which is, however, provisional and the arguments defeasible. When used improperly they can be fallacious.[30]
Uses
Argumentation schemes are useful for argument identification, argument analysis, argument evaluation, and argument invention.
Argument identification is the identification of arguments in a text or spoken discourse. Many or most of the statements will not be arguments or parts of arguments. But some of those statements might look similar to arguments. Informal logicians have especially noted the similarity between words used to express arguments and those used to express explanations.[31] Words like "because" or "since" can be used to introduce reasons that justify argumentative positions, but they can also be used to introduce explanations: e.g., "something is the way it is because of the following explanation". Schemes may aid in argument identification because they describe more factors that distinguish the argument type from other text. For example, an argument from expert opinion refers to an expert and a field of expertise. Some schemes contain more readily distinguished characteristics than others.
Argument analysis is distinguishing the premises and conclusion of an argument and determining their relationships (such as linked or convergent), determining the form of inference, making explicit any implicit premises or conclusions. (These are the tasks of analysis from a logical perspective. When discourse and rhetorical analyses are considered, there would be additional tasks.)
The logical analysis of arguments is especially made difficult by the presence of implicit elements.[32] Their being implicit means that they are not present in the text (or spoken discourse) as statements; nevertheless, they are understood by the reader or hearer because of nonverbal elements or because of shared background knowledge from the social, cultural, or other shared, context. The implicit elements are also elements that are needed to make the argument cogent. Arguments containing implicit elements are called enthymemes, which is a term that was used by Aristotle in his works about dialectical reasoning and argument. If an argument appears to match a scheme but is missing some elements, it could be used as a guide to determining what is implicit in the argument.[33] An additional challenge with regard to this task could be that some schemes are easy to confuse. In Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca's concept of argumentative scheme, different schemes could apply to the same argument depending on the interpretation of the argument or the argument could be described by multiple schemes.[34] Hansen and Walton also write that arguments may fit multiple schemes.[35]
Argument evaluation is the determination of the goodness of the argument: determining how good the argument is and whether, or with what reservations, it ought to be accepted. As previously mentioned, in schemes accompanied by critical questions, a measure of the goodness of the argument is whether the critical questions can be appropriately answered. In other schemes, as in the example of the Groarke and Tindale versions of argument from expert opinion, only good arguments fit the scheme because the criteria for goodness are included as premises.[36] If any one of them is false, the conclusion should not be accepted.
Argument invention is making new arguments to suit the occasion. As mentioned above Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca attribute that use to the loci and topoi of the classical argumentation theorists. They form a catalog of argument types from which arguers may draw in constructing their arguments. With argumentation schemes described by their structure with single letter variables as placeholders, constructing such arguments is just a matter of filling in the placeholders. Of course the arguer might use other words that convey the same meaning and embellish the argument in other ways.
Argument mining
Argument mining is the automatic identification of arguments in natural language using computing technology. Some of the tasks of argument analysis are also intended to be accomplished automatically as a part of argument mining. The same benefits from the use of argumentation schemes as described above for identification and analysis are relevant to argument mining. More linguistic features that distinguish specific schemes can be used by the computer algorithms to identify instances of those schemes and therefore identify the arguments that are of those kinds. Without having noticed such argumentative patterns only features common to all arguments would be available. Feng and Hirst in 2011 proposed using argumentation schemes to (automatically) help fill in missing (implicit) premises in arguments and experimented with detecting instances of such schemes.[37] Similar work was done by Lawrence and Reed, and reported in 2016.[38]
References
- ^ Aristotle (1991). Rhetoric. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- ^ van Eemeren, Frans; Grootendorst, Rob (1992). Argumentation, communication, and fallacies: A pragma-dialectical perspective. Hillsdale: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.
- ^ Toulmin, S.; Rieke, R.; Janik, A. (1984). An introduction to reasoning. New York: Macmillan Publishing Company.
- ^ Kienpointner, Manfred (1992). Alltagslogik: Struktur und Funktion von Argumentationsmustern. Stuttgart: Fromman-Holzboog.
- ^ Aristotle (1991). Topics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
- ^ Stump, Eleonore (2004). Boethius's "De topicis differentiis". Ithaca and London: Cornell UP.
- ^ Cicero, Marcus Tullius (2003). Topica. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
- ^ Rigotti, Eddo; Greco Morasso, Sara (2019). Inference in argumentation: A topics-based approach to argument schemes. Amsterdam: Springer.
- ^ Walton, Douglas; Reed, Chris; Macagno, Fabrizio (2008). Argumentation Schemes. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
- ^ Table from Douglas Walton, Fundamentals of Critical Argumentation (New York: Cambridge University Press, 2006), 86.
- ^ Walton, 86.
- ^ ChaÏm Perelman and L. Olbrechts-Tyteca, The New Rhetoric: A Treatise on Argumentation, trans. John Wilkinson and Purcell Weaver (Notre Dame, Indiana: University of Notre Dame Press, 1969), 9.
- ^ Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, 187.
- ^ Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, 190.
- ^ Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, 83.
- ^ Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, 83.
- ^ Walton, Reed, and Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, 276.
- ^ Walton, Reed, and Macagno, 3; Arthur C. Hastings, "A Reformulation of the Modes of Reasoning in Argumentation" (Northwestern University, Evanston, Illinois, 1963); For extensive review of the history, see also Walton, Reed, and Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, chap. 8 and section 7.3 for information about Hastings' treatment of argumentation schemes.
- ^ See, for example, Walton, Fundamentals of Critical Argumentation, 72–73.
- ^ Douglas Walton, Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Publishers, 1996), 21.
- ^ Walton, Reed, and Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, 1–2.
- ^ For deductive and probabilistic, see Christoph Lumer, "Argument Schemes--an Epistemological Approach," in OSSA Conference Archive, 2011, sec. 2.1 and 5, https://scholar.uwindsor.ca/ossaarchive/OSSA9/papersandcommentaries/17; For another probabilistic approach, see Ulrike Hahn, Mike Oaksford, and Adam J.L. Harris, "Testimony and Argument: A Bayesian Approach," in Bayesian Argumentation: The Practical Side of Probability, ed. Frank Zenker, Synthese Library 362 (Dordrecht: Springer, 2013), 15–38, doi:10.1007/978-94-007-5357-0_2.
- ^ Tables from Walton, Reed, and Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, 310.
- ^ Walton, Reed, and Macagno, 15.
- ^ Nicholas Rescher, Dialectics: A Controversy-Oriented Approach to the Theory of Knowledge (Albany: State University of New York Press, 1977), 47, 60.
- ^ Walton, Argumentation Schemes for Presumptive Reasoning, 112.
- ^ Walton, 112.
- ^ Walton, Reed, and Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, 327.
- ^ Charles L. Hamblin, Fallacies (London: Methuen, 1970), chap. 1.
- ^ Trevor Bench-Capon and Katie Atkinson, "Argumentation Schemes: From Informal Logic to Computational Models," in Dialectics, Dialogue, and Argumentation: An Examination of Douglas Walton's Theories of Reasoning and Argument, ed. Chris Reed and Christopher W. Tindale, vol. 12, Tributes (London: College Publications, 2010), 103.
- ^ Hans V. Hansen and Douglas Walton, "Argument Kinds and Argument Roles in the Ontario Provincial Election," Journal of Argumentation in Context 2, no. 2 (2013): sec. 6.5; Douglas Walton, "Argumentation Schemes and Their Application in Argument Mining," in Studies in Critical Thinking, ed. J. Anthony Blair, Digital Edition, vol. 8, Windsor Studies in Argumentation (Center for Research in Reasoning, Argumentation and Rhetoric, 2019), 178.
- ^ Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, The New Rhetoric, 177; Walton, "Argumentation Schemes and Their Application in Argument Mining," 208–9.
- ^ Walton, Reed, and Macagno, Argumentation Schemes, 189; Vanessa Wei Feng and Graeme Hirst, "Classifying Arguments by Scheme," in Proceedings of the 49th Annual Meeting of the Association for Computational Linguistics: Human Language Technologies-Volume 1, 2011, 987.
- ^ Perelman and Olbrechts-Tyteca, The New Rhetoric, 187–88.
- ^ Hansen and Walton, "Argument Kinds and Argument Roles in the Ontario Provincial Election," sec. 7.3.
- ^ Hans V. Hansen, "Argument Scheme Theory" (European Conference on Argumentation, European Conference on Argumentation (ECA), Proceedings (forthcoming), 2019).
- ^ Feng and Hirst, "Classifying Arguments by Scheme."
- ^ John Lawrence and Chris Reed, "Argument Mining Using Argumentation Scheme Structures," in Proceedings of COMMA 2016 (Computational Models of Argument, Amsterdam: IOS Press, 2016), 379–90.