Jump to content

User:Anypodetos/sandbox

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Anypodetos (talk | contribs) at 11:08, 16 December 2018 (+). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

Implicature is a term used in pragmatics, a subdiscipline of linguistics. It was coined by H. P. Grice in 1975 to refer to what is suggested or implied in an utterance, even though it is not literally expressed.[1] Take the for example the following exchange:

A (to passer by): I am out of gas.
B: There is a gas station round the corner.

Here, B does not say, but implicates, that the gas station is open.[2][3]

Later linguists introduced refined and different definitions of the term, leading to somewhat different ideas about which parts of the information conveyed by an utterance are actually implicatures and which aren't.[4][5]

Conversational implicature

Grice was primarily concerned with the type of implicature he called conversational. These arise because communicating people are expected by their addressees to obey Grice's maxims of conversation and the overarching cooperative principle, which basically states that people are expected to communicate in a cooperative, helpful way.[6][7]

The maxims of conversation The maxim of Quality
try to make your contribution one that is true, specifically:
(i) do not say what you believe to be false
(ii) do not say that for which you lack adequate evidence
The maxim of Quantity
(i) make your contribution as informative as is required for the current purposes of the exchange
(ii) do not make your contribution more informative than is required
The maxim of Relevance [or Relation]
make your contributions relevant
The maxim of Manner
be perspicious, and specifically:
(i) avoid obscurity
(ii) avoid ambiguity
(iii) be brief
(iv) be orderly [6]

Standard implicatures

The "standard" situation is where the addressee can draw conclusions from the assumption that the communicator obeys the maxims, as in the following examples. The symbol "+>" means "implicates".[8]

Quality
It is raining. +> I believe, and have adequate evidence, that it is raining.

Moore's paradox, the observation that the sentence "It is raining, but I don't believe that it is raining" sounds contradictory although it isn't from a strictly logical point of view, has been explained as a contradiction to this type of implicature. However, as implicatures can be cancelled (see below), this explanation is dubious.[8]

Quantity
The flag is green. +> The flag is completely green.

If the flag contained any other features, the utterance would not be informative enough. Such scalar implicatures are treated in more detail below.

Relation/relevance
That cake looks delicious. +> I would like a piece of that cake.

The statement taken by itself would be irrelevant in most situations.

The introductory example of an implicature also belongs here:

A: I am out of gas.
B: There is a gas station round the corner. +> The gas station is open.
Manner
The cowboy jumped on his horse and rode into the sunset. +> The cowboy performed these two action in this order.

Clashes of maxims

.[9]

Floutings

.[10]

Quality
Quantity
Relation/relevance
Manner


Generalized conversational implicatures (WHERE?)

Properties

Conversational implicatures are defeasible (cancellable), meaning that the implicature may be cancelled with further information or context.[11] Take the example from above:

That cake looks delicious. +> I would like a piece of that cake.
That cake looks delicious, but it looks too rich for me.

non-detachable, calculable, non-conventional

Lastly, conversational implicatures are context dependent. This means that an utterance will not necessarily give rise to the same implicatures if said in a different context.

Neo-Gricean accounts

...........

While implicatures are not usually entailed by the utterance, there are exceptions:

A: Did you drive somewhere yesterday?
B: I drove to London.

Here, B implicates via the maxim of relation that he drove somewhere, but this is also entailed by his answer.[12][13]

Implicature in relevance theory

Kiwifruit

In the framework known as relevance theory, implicature is defined as a counterpart to explicature. The explicatures of an utterance are the communicated assumptions that are developed from its logical form (intuitively, the literal meaning) by supplying additional information from context: by disambiguating ambiguous expressions, assigning references to pronouns and other variables, and so on. All communicated assumptions that cannot be obtained in this way are implicatures. For example, if Peter says

Susan told me that her kiwis were too sour.

the hearer might arrive at the explicature

Susan told Peter that the kiwifruit she, Susan, grew were too sour for the judges at the fruit grower's contest.

Now assume that Peter and the hearer both know that

Susan is ambitious. If she loses at something, she's pretty downcast.

and that Peter intended the hearer to activate this knowledge. Then this is an implicated premise. Further, if Peter intended the hearer to conclude from his utterance and the implicated premise that

Susan needs to be cheered up.
Peter wants me to ring Susan and cheer her up.

then these are implicated conclusions. Implicated premises and conclusions are the two types of implicatures in the relevance theoretical sense.[14][15]

Scalar implicature

Scalar implicature is a type of conversational quantity implicature. Prototypical examples include the words "some", "few", or "many". For example:[16][17]

John ate some of the cookies.

Here, the use of "some" semantically entails that more than one cookie was eaten. It does not entail, but implicates, that not every cookie was eaten.

I only need a few cupcakes for the dinner tomorrow.

Here, the use of "a few" semantically entails that more than one cupcake is needed, while it implicates that not many are needed for the dinner.

..............[18]

The flag is green. +> The flag is completely green.

At least some "scalar implicatures" seem not to be implicatures at all................[19][20]

Conventional implicature

Conventional implicatures, briefly introduced but never elaborated on by Grice, are independent of the cooperative principle and the four maxims. They are instead tied to the conventional meaning of certain words and grammatical structures. In addition, they are not defeasible, but have the force of entailments.[21][22] An example:

Donovan is poor but happy.

This sentence states that Donovan is poor, and that he is happy. In addition, the word "but" implicates a sense of contrast. Taken together, the sentence means approximately "Surprisingly, Donovan is happy in spite of being poor".

"Yewberry", more accurately the arillus of the European yew

An example of a grammatical structure producing conventional implicatures is the appositive:[23]

Yewberry jelly, toxic in the extreme, will give you an awful stomachache.

The implicature here is that yewberry jelly is toxic in the extreme. Because of the mentioned differences to conversational implicatures, it has been argued that "conventional implicatures" aren't implicatures at all but rather secondary propositions of an utterance. Under this view, the sentence about Donovan would have the primary proposition "Donovan is poor and happy" and the additional proposition "There is a contrast between poverty and happiness". The sentence about yewberry jelly contains the two propositions "Yewberry jelly will give you an awful stomachache" and "Yewberry jelly is toxic in the extreme".[24]

See also

References

Bibliography

  • Bach, Kent (1999). "The Myth of Conventional Implicature" (PDF). Linguistics and Philosophy. 22 (4). {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Bach, Kent (2006), The Top 10 Misconceptions about Implicature (PDF) In: Birner & Ward (2006).
  • Birner, Betty (2013). Introduction to Pragmatics. Chichester, West Sussex, UK: Wiley-Blackwell. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Birner, Betty; Ward, Gregory (2006). A Festschrift for Larry Horn. Amsterdam: John Benjamins. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Blackburn, Simon (1996). The Oxford Dictionary of Philosophy. Oxford University Press. Implicature. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Blome‐Tillmann, Michael (2013). "Conversational Implicatures (and How to Spot Them)" (PDF). Philosophy Compass. 8 (2): 170–185. doi:10.1111/phc3.12003.
  • Carston, Robyn (1998). Informativeness, Relevance and Scalar Implicature (PDF). John Benjamins. ISBN 978-1556193309. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help); Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Carston, Robyn (2002). Thoughts and Utterances: The Pragmatics of Explicit Communication. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-0631214885. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Cole, Peter, The synchronic and diachronic status of conversational implicature. In Cole & Morgan (1975:257–288).
  • Cole, Peter; Morgan, Jerry L., eds. (1975). Syntax and Semantics, 3: Speech Acts. New York: Academic Press. ISBN 978-0-12-785424-3. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Davis, S., ed. (1991). Pragmatics: A Reader. Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-505898-7. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Davison, A., Indirect speech acts and what to do with them. In Cole & Morgan (1975:143–184).
  • Green, G. M., How to get people to do things with words. In Cole & Morgan (1975:107–141).
  • Grice, H. P., ed. (1989). Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press. ISBN 978-0-674-85270-9. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Grice, H. P. (1975), Logic and conversation (PDF). Cole & Morgan (1975). Reprinted in Grice (1989:22–40).
  • Hancher, Michael (1978). "Grice's "Implicature" and Literary Interpretation: Background and Preface". Twentieth Annual Meeting Midwest Modern Language Association.
  • Holtgraves, Thomas; Kraus, Brian (2018). "Processing scalar implicatures in conversational contexts: An ERP study". Journal of Neurolinguistics. 46: 93–108. doi:10.1016/j.jneuroling.2017.12.008. {{cite journal}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Levinson, Stephen (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge University Press. ISBN 978-0521294140.
  • Potts, Christopher (2005). "Conventional implicatures, a distinguished class of meanings" (PDF). The Oxford Handbook of Linguistic Interfaces. Oxford University Press. {{cite web}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Searle, John, Indirect speech acts. In Cole & Morgan (1975). Reprinted in Davis (1991:265–277).
  • Sperber, Dan; Wilson, Deirdre (1996). Relevance: Communication and Cognition. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-0631198789. {{cite book}}: Invalid |ref=harv (help)
  • Wilson, Deirdre; Sperber, Dan (1981). Werth, Paul (ed.). On Grice's Theory of Conversation. Croom Helm. pp. 155–178. ISBN 9780709927174. {{cite book}}: |work= ignored (help); Invalid |ref=harv (help)

Further reading

Category:Pragmatics Category:Inference