Jump to content

Pure inductive logic

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Aksvocnev (talk | contribs) at 14:35, 27 April 2018 (Created page with '{{User sandbox}} <!-- EDIT BELOW THIS LINE --> =Pure Inductive Logic= Pure inductive logic (PIL) is the area of mathematics concerned with the theoretical and...'). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.
(diff) ← Previous revision | Latest revision (diff) | Newer revision → (diff)

This sandbox is in the article namespace. Either move this page into your userspace, or remove the {{User sandbox}} template.

Pure Inductive Logic

Pure inductive logic (PIL) is the area of mathematics concerned with the theoretical and mathematical foundations of inductive logic [1]. It combines classical predicate logic and probability theory. Probability values are assigned to sentences of a first order relational language to represent degrees of belief that should be held by a rational agent. Conditional probability values represent degrees of belief on the basis of some evidence.

PIL studies prior probability functions on the set of sentences and evaluaes rationality of such prior probability functions via proposing principles that such functions should satisfy. Each of the principles guarantees that, in some respect, the function assigns probability values to sentences rationally and that also the derived assignments of conditional probability values given some evidence are rational.

History

Inductive logic started to take a clearer shape in the early 20th century in the work of William Ernest Johnson and John Maynard Keynes , and was further developed by Rudolf Carnap. Carnap introduced the distinction between pure and applied inductive logic,[1], and the modern Pure Inductive Logic [2] evolves within the pure, uninterpreted approach envisaged by Carnap.

Framework

Pure Inductive Logic uses first order predicate logic without equality, with the usual connectives (and, or, not and implies respectively), quantifiers , finitely many predicate (relation) symbols and countably many constant symbols

There are no function symbols. The predicate symbols can be unary, binary or of higher arities. The finite set of predicate symbols may vary whist the rest of the language is fixed. It is a convention to refer to the language as and write

where the list the predicate symbols. The set of all sentences is denoted . If a sentence is written with constants appearing in it listed then it is assumed that the list includes all those that appear. is the set of structures for with universe and with each constant symbol interpreted as itself.

A probability function for sentences of is a function with domain and values in the real interval satisfying Kolmogorov's axioms and Gaifman's condition on quantified sentences which postulates that the constant symbols name all individuals. That is:

- any logically valid sentence has probability 1:

- if sentences and are mutually exclusive then

- for a formula with one free variable the probability of is the limit of probabilities of as tends to .

For and a sentence with , the conditional probability function is defined by

Unlike belief functions in many valued logics [2], it is not the case that the probability value of a compound sentence is determined by the probability values of its components. Probability respects the classical semantics: logically equivalent sentences must be given the same probability value. Hence logically equivalent sentences are often identified.

A state description for a finite set of constants is a conjunction of predicates (or their negations) instantiated exclusively by these constants, and such that for any such eligible atomic sentence either it or its negation appear in the conjunction.

Any probability function is uniquely determined by its values on state descriptions. To define a probability functions, it suffices to specify nonnegative values of all state descriptions for (for all ) so that the values of all state descriptions for extending a given state description for sum to the value of the state description they all extend, with the convention that the (only) state description for no constants is a tautology and that has value 1.

If is a state description for a set of constants including then it is said that are indiscernible in , , just when upon adding equality to the language (and axioms of equality to the logic), the sentence would be consistent.

In unary PIL, all the predicates are unary. Formulae of the form

where stands for one of , , are called atoms. It is assumed that they are listed in some fixed order as . A state description specifies an atom for each constant involved in it, and it can be written as a conjunction of these atoms instantiated by the corresponding constants. Two constants are indiscernible in the state description if it specifies the same atom for them.

Central question

Assume a rational agent inhabits a structure for the language but knows nothing about which one it is. What probability function should he adopt when is to represent his degree of belief that a sentence is true in this ambient structure?

Rational Principles

The following principles have been proposed as desirable properties of a rational prior probability function for .

The Constant Exchangeability Principle, Ex. The probability of a sentence does not change when the in it are replaced by any other -tuple of (distinct) constants.

The Principle of Predicate Exchangeability, Px. If are predicates of the same arity then for a sentence ,

where is the result of simultaneously replacing by and by throughout .

The Strong Negation Principle, SN. For a predicate and sentence ,

where is the result of simultaneously replacing by and by throughout .

The Principle of Regularity, Reg. If a quantifier-free sentence is satisfiable then .

The Principle of Super Regularity (Universal Certainty), SReg. If a senctence is satisfiable then .

The Constant Irrelevance Principle, IP. If sentences have no constants in common then .

The Weak Irrelevance Principle, WIP. If sentences have no constant nor predicates in common then .

Language Invariance Principle, Li. There is a family of probability functions , one on each language , all satisfying Px and Ex, and such that and if all predicates of belong also to then and agree on sentences of .

The (Strong) Counterpart Principle, CP. If are sentences such that is the result of replacing some constant/relation symbols in by new constant/relation symbols of the same arity not occurring in then

(SCP) If moreover is the result of replacing the same and possibly also other constant/relation symbols in by new constant/relation symbols of the same arity not occurring in then

The Invariance Principle, INV. If is an isomorphism of the Lindenbaum-Tarski algebra of supported by some permutation of in the sense that for sentences ,

just when

then .

The Permutation Invariance Principle, PIP. As INV except that is additionally required to map (equivalence classes of) state descriptions to the same.

The Spectrum Exchangeability Principle, Sx. The probability of a state description depends only on the spectrum of , that is, on the multiset of sizes of equivalence classes with respect to the equivalence .

Li with Sx. As the Language Invariance Principle but all the probability functions in the family also satisfy Spectrum Exchangeability.

The Principle of Induction, PI. Let be a state description and a constant not appearing in . Let , be state descriptions extending to include . If is -equivalent to some and at least as many constants as it is -equivalent to then .

Further Rational Principles for Unary PIL

The Principle of Instantial Relevance, PIR. For a sentence , atom and constants not appearing in ,

.

The Generalized Principle of Instantial Relevance, GPIR. For quantifier-free sentences with constants not appearing in , if then

Johnson Sufficientness Principle, JSP. For atoms , the probability : depends only on and on the number of times appears amongst the .

The Principle of Atom Exchangeability, Ax. If is a permutation of and is a state description expressed as a conjunction of instantiated atoms then where obtains from upon replacing each by .

Reichenbach's Axiom, RA. Let for be an infinite sequence of atoms and an atom. Then as tends to , the difference between the conditional probability

and the proportion of occurrences of amongst the tends to 0.

Unary Language Invariance Principle, ULi. As Li, but with languages restricted to the unary ones.

ULi with Ax. As ULi but all the probability functions in the family also satisfy Atom Exchangeability.

Recovery Whenever is a state description then there is another state description such that and for any quantifier free sentence ,

Relationships between Principles

LI implies Ex and Px (by definition).

LI implies CP and SCP.

Li with Sx implies PI.

INV implies PIP and Ex.

PIP+Ex implies Sx.

In the unary case, Ex implies PIR

In the unary case, Ax is equivalent to PIP.

In the unary case, Ax+Ex is equivalent to Sx.

Important Probability Functions

Functions . For a given structure for and ,

Functions . For a given state description , is defined via specifying its values for state descriptions as follows. is the probability that when are randomly picked from , with replacement and according to the uniform distribution, then

Functions . As above but employing a non-standard universe (starting with possibly non-standard state descriptions and infinitely large ) to obtain the standard .

The are the only probability functions that satisfy Ex and IP.

Functions . For a given infinite sequence of non-negative reals such that

and ,

is defined via specifying its values for state descriptions as follows.

For a sequence of natural numbers (possibly 0) and a state description , is consistent with if whenever then . is the number of state descriptions for consistent with . is the sum over those with which is compatible, of

The are the only probability functions that satisfy Li with Sx and WIP. (The language invariant family witnessing Li with Sx consists of the functions with fixed , where is as but defined with language .)

Further, Unary Probability Functions

Functions . For a vector of non-negative real numbers summing to one, is defined via specifying its values for state descriptions as follows:

The are the only probability functions that satisfy Ex and IP (they are also expressible as ).

Carnap Continuum functions . For , the probability function is uniquely determined by the values

where the is number of times occurs amongst the . Furthermore, is the probability function that assigns to every state description for constants and is the probability function that assigns to any state description in which all constants are indiscernible, 0 to any other state description.

The are the only probability functions that satisfy Ex and JSP.

Functions . For , is the average of the functions where has all but one coordinate equal to each other with the odd coordinate differing from them by , so

where , ( in </math>i</math>th place) and .

For , the are equal to for

The are the only functions that satisfy GPIR, Ex, Ax and Reg.

The with are the only functions that satisfy Recovery, Reg and Uli with Ax.

Representation Theorems

A representation theorem for a class of probability functions provides means of expressing every probability function in the class in terms of generic, relatively simple probability functions from the same class.

Represetation theorem for all probability functions. Every probability function for can be represented as

where is a -additive measure on the -algebra of subsets of generated by the sets

Representation theorem for Ex (employing non-standard analysis and Loeb Integration Theory). Every probability function for satisfying Ex can be represented as

where is an internal set of state descriptions and is a -additive measure on a -algebra of subsets of .

Representation theorem for Sx. Every probability function for satisfying Sx can be represented as

where is the set of sequences

of non-negative reals summing to 1 and such that , and is a -additive measure on the Borel subsets of in the product topology..

de Finetti Representation Theorem (unary). In the unary case (where is a language containing unary predicates), the representation theorem for Ex is equivalent to:

Every probability function for satisfying Ex can be represented as

where is the set of vectors of non-negative real numbers summing to one and is a -additive measure on .

References

  1. ^ Rudolf Carnap (1980). A Basic System of Inductive Logic, in Studies in Inductive Logic and Probability, Volume 1, pp 69f.
  2. ^ Jeff Paris, Alena Vencovská (2015). Pure Inductive Logic, Cambridge University Press.