Jump to content

Projective object

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Siddharthist (talk | contribs) at 22:35, 17 October 2017 (Add definition that applies to non-locally small categories, with commutative diagram. Add "Properties" section. Add citations to nLab, Awodey, and Mac Lane. Add example that sets are projective iff the axiom of choice holds.). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

In category theory, the notion of a projective object generalizes the notion of a projective module.

An object in a category is projective if for any epimorphism and morphism , there is a morphism such that , i.e. the following diagram commutes:

That is, every morphism factors through every epimorphism .[1][2]

In a locally small category , the following statement is equivalent: is projective if the hom functor

preserves epimorphisms.[3]

Let be an abelian category. In this context, an object is called a projective object if

is an exact functor, where is the category of abelian groups.

The dual notion of a projective object is that of an injective object: An object in a locally small abelian category is injective if the functor from to is exact.

Properties

  • The coproduct of two projective objects is projective.[4]
  • The retract of a projective object is projective.[5]

Enough projectives

Let be an abelian category. is said to have enough projectives if, for every object of , there is a projective object of and an exact sequence

In other words, the map is "epic", or an epimorphism.

Examples

The statement that all sets are projective is equivalent to the axiom of choice.

Let be a ring with 1. Consider the (abelian) category of left -modules . The projective objects in are precisely the projective left R-modules. Consequently, is itself a projective object in Dually, the injective objects in are exactly the injective left R-modules.

The category of left (right) -modules also has enough projectives. This is true since, for every left (right) -module , we can take to be the free (and hence projective) -module generated by a generating set for (we can in fact take to be ). Then the canonical projection is the required surjection.

References

  1. ^ "projective object in nLab". ncatlab.org. Retrieved 2017-10-17.
  2. ^ Awodey, Steve (2010). Category theory (2nd ed ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 33. ISBN 9780199237180. OCLC 740446073. {{cite book}}: |edition= has extra text (help)
  3. ^ Mac Lane, Saunders (1978). Categories for the Working Mathematician (Second edition ed.). New York, NY: Springer New York. p. 114. ISBN 1441931236. OCLC 851741862. {{cite book}}: |edition= has extra text (help)
  4. ^ Awodey, Steve (2010). Category theory (2nd ed ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 72. ISBN 9780199237180. OCLC 740446073. {{cite book}}: |edition= has extra text (help)
  5. ^ Awodey, Steve (2010). Category theory (2nd ed ed.). Oxford: Oxford University Press. p. 33. ISBN 9780199237180. OCLC 740446073. {{cite book}}: |edition= has extra text (help)

This article incorporates material from Projective object on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.

This article incorporates material from Enough projectives on PlanetMath, which is licensed under the Creative Commons Attribution/Share-Alike License.