User:TestFunction/sandbox
In combinatorial mathematics, the hook-length formula gives dλ, the number of Young tableau of shape λ, as a function of the hook-lengths of λ. It has applications to representation theory and the problem of longest increasing subsequences.
Let λ = {λ1,λ2,…,λm} be a partition of n. That is, λ1,λ2,…,λm are positive integers such that n = λ1 + λ2 + … + λm and λ1 ≥ λ2 ≥ … ≥ λm. Then the Young diagram of shape λ, denoted Y(λ), is an array of cells with indices (i,j) where 1 ≤ i ≤ m and 1 ≤ j ≤ λi. The Young diagram of shape λ has n cells and has a natural bijection to a partition of n. A standard Young tableau of shape λ is a Young diagram of shape λ in which each of the n cells contains a distinct integer between 1 and n (i.e., no repetition), such that each row and each column form increasing sequences. For each cell (i,j) of Y(λ), the hook Hλ(i,j) is the set of all cells (a,b) such that a=i and b≥j or a≥i and b=j. The hook-length hλ(i,j) is defined as |Hλ(i,j)|, the number of cells in the hook Hλ(i,j). [1]
Then the hook-length formula is
There are other formulas for dλ, but the hook-length formula is particularly simple. Indeed, the hook-length formula was discovered in 1954 by J. S. Frame, G. de B. Robinson, and R. M. Thrall by improving a less convenient determinant formula for dλ. [2] This earlier formula was deduced independently by G. Frobenius and A. Young in 1900 and 1902 respectively using algebraic methods. [3] [4] P. A. MacMahon found an alternate proof for the Young-Frobenius formula in 1916 using difference methods. [5]
Since its discovery in 1954, many alternate proofs for the hook-length formula have been found in hopes of a simpler proof. Knuth comments that a simple result should have a simple result, although his "proof" The first bijective proof was found by Remmel in 1982 (but isn't prob proof also bijective?) Also because despite the simplicity of the hook-length formula, it was not clear why hooks appeared in the formula. Hillman and Grassl gave the first proof that illuminates the role of hooks in 1976. They proved (via a combinatorial bijection) a special case of Stanley hook-content formula, which is known to imply the hook-length formula. C. Greene, A. Nijenhuis, and H. S. Wilf found a probabilistic proof in which the hook lengths appear naturally in 1979. [6] A direct bijective proof was first discovered by D. S. Franzblau and D. Zeilberger in 1982. [7] A simpler bijective proof was announced by Igor Pak and Alexander V. Stoyanovskii in 1992, and its complete proof was presented by the pair and Jean-Christophe Novelli in 1997. [8] [9]
References
- ^ Greene, C., Nijenhuis, A. and Wilf, H. S. (1979). A probabilistic proof of a formula for the number of Young tableaux of a given shape. Adv. in Math. 31, 104–109.
- ^ Frame, J. S., Robinson, G. de B. and Thrall, R. M. (1954). The hook graphs of the symmetric group. Canad. J. Math. 6, 316–325.
- ^ G. Frobenius, Uber die charaktere der symmetrischer gruppe, Preuss. &ad. Wk. sitz. (1900), 516-534.
- ^ A. Young, Quantitative substitutional analysis II, Proc. London Math. Sot., Ser. 1, 35 (1902), 361-397.
- ^ P. A. MacMahon, “Combinatory Analysis,” Cambridge Univ. Press, London/New York, 1916; reprinted by Chelsea, New York, 1960.
- ^ Greene, C., Nijenhuis, A. and Wilf, H. S. (1979). A probabilistic proof of a formula for the number of Young tableaux of a given shape. Adv. in Math. 31, 104–109.
- ^ Franzblau, D. S. and Zeilberger, D. (1982). A bijective proof of the hook-length formula. J. Algorithms 3, 317–343.
- ^ Pak, I. M. and Stoyanovskii, A. V. (1992). A bijective proof of the hook-length formula. Funct. Anal. Appl. 24.
- ^ Novelli, J.-C., Pak, I. M. and Stoyanovskii, A. V. (1997). A direct bijective proof of the hook-length formula. Discrete Mathematics and Theoretical Computer Science 1, 1997, 53–67.
Since then, it has been reproved, generalized and extended in several different ways. Applications have been found in a number of fields ranging from algebraic geometry to probability, and from group theory to the analysis of algorithms. Still, the hook length formula remains deeply mysterious and its full depth is yet to be completely understood.
Knuth wrote in 1973, “Since the hook-lengths formula is such a simple result, it deserves
a simple proof ...”
Since then, it has been reproved, generalized and extended
in several different ways, and applications have been found in a number of fields ranging from
algebraic geometry to probability, and from group theory to the analysis of algorithms. Still,
the hook length formula remains deeply mysterious and its full depth is yet to be completely understood.
Hillman and Grassl provided in 1976 proof uses hooks in a natural way to derive a combinatorial correspondence involving plane partitions, from which the Frame-Robinson-Thrall formula can be derived by an asymptotic argument.
Stanley 1972 Hillman and Grassl provided in 1976 proof uses hooks in a natural way to derive a combinatorial correspondence involving plane partitions, from which the Frame-Robinson-Thrall formula can be derived by an asymptotic argument.
For the latter, the bijection without the complete proof was announced in 1992 by presented fully proven its proof was fully preseneted complete proof was presented
In combinatorial mathematics, the hook-length formula is … (a few paragraphs explaining what it's about, who proved it and when).