Philosophical objections to Cantor's Theory
![]() | This article possibly contains original research. |
Georg Cantor's argument that there are sets that have a cardinality (or "power" or "number") that is greater than the (already infinite) cardinality of the whole numbers 1,2,3,... has probably attracted more hostility than any other theoretical argument, before or since. Logician Wilfrid Hodges has commented on the energy devoted to refuting this "harmless little argument". What had it done to anyone to make them angry with it?
This article summarises the argument and examines some of the objections that have been raised against it.
Cantor's Argument
Cantor's 1891 argument is that there exists an infinite set (which he identifies with the set of real numbers), which has a larger number of elements, or as he puts it, has a greater 'power' (Mächtigkeit), than the infinite set of finite whole numbers 1, 2, 3, ...
There are a number of steps implicit in his argument, as follows
- That the elements of no set can be put into one-to-one correspondence with all of its subsets. This is known as Cantor's Theorem. It depends on very few of the assumptions of set theory, and (as John P. Mayberry puts it, is a "simple and beautiful argument" that is "pregnant with consequences". Few have seriously questioned this step of the argument.
- That the concept of "having the same number" can be captured by the idea of one-one correlation. This (purely definitional) assumption is sometimes known as Hume's principle. As Frege points out, "If a waiter wishes to be certain of laying exactly as many knives on a table as plates, he has no need to count either of them; all he has to do is to lay immediately to the right of every plate a knife, taking care that every knife on the table lies immediately to the right of a plate. Plates and knifes are thus correlated one to one" (1884, tr. 1953, §70).
- That there exists at least one infinite set of things, usually identified with the set of all finite whole numbers or "natural numbers". This assumption (not formally specified by Cantor) is captured in formal set theory by the Axiom of Infinity. This assumption allows us to prove, together with Cantor's theorem, that there exists at least one set that cannot be correlated one one with all its subsets. It does not prove, however, that there in fact exists any set corresponding to "all the subsets".
- That there does indeed exist a set of all subsets of the natural numbers is captured in formal set theory by the Power set axiom, which says that for every set there is a set of all of its subsets. This allows us to prove Cantor's assertion that there exists a set with a greater number of elements than the set of natural numbers. The set N of natural numbers exists (by the Axiom of Infinity), and so does the set R of all its subsets (by the Power set axiom). By Cantor's theorem, R cannot be one one correlated with N, and by Cantor's definition of number of "power", it can be shown that R has a greater number than N. QED.
Reception of the Argument
From the start, Cantor's Theory was controversial among mathematicians and (later) philosophers.
I don't know what predominates in Cantor's theory - philosophy or theology, but I am sure that there is no mathematics there (Kronecker)
Later generations will regard [Cantor's] set theory as a disease from which one has recovered (Poincare 1908, see endnote)
Before Cantor, the notion of infinity was often taken as a useful abstraction which helped mathematicians reason about the finite world, for example the use of infinite limit cases in calculus. The infinite was deemed to have at most a potential existence, rather than an actual existence.
Actual infinity does not exist. What we call infinite is only the endless possibility of creating new objects no matter how many exist already (Poincare quoted from Kline 1982)
Many mathematicians, along with Leopold Kronecker argued that the completed infinite may be part of philosophy or theology, but that it has no proper place in mathematics.
Cantor's ideas ultimately were accepted, strongly supported by David Hilbert, amongst others. Even constructivists and the intuitionists, who developed their schools of mathematics as a reaction to Cantor's infinitary ideas, generally no longer argue that mathematicians should abandon Cantor's Theory. It would appear that Hilbert's prediction has proved accurate:
"No one will drive us from the paradise which Cantor created for us" (Hilbert, 1926)
(To which Wittgenstein replied "if one person can see it as a paradise of mathematicians, why should not another see it as a joke? (RFM V. 7)).
Naïve objections
Objections to Cantor's proof (together with objections to Gödel's theorem) are a standard feature of mathematical Usenet discussions. These are generally flawed in some way.
Many of these objections depend on objections to step two of the argument. These typically use applications of the pigeon-hole principle [reference], or other assumptions that require "counting" all the natural numbers. Thus they rely on the assumption that we can "count" all such numbers by a process that at some point comes to an end. This is what Cantorians deny. They say this begs the question. Of course we can count finite numbers, indeed this constitutes one definition of a finite number. But who is to say that all numbers are finite, given that Hume's principle shows that infinite sets can also be compared in size? Cantor argued in his philosophical writing and correspondence that all objections based on the finitude of our "normal" concept of number, thus involve a petitio principii.
All so-called proofs against the possibility of actually infinite numbers are faulty, as can be demonstrated in every particular case, and as can be concluded on general grounds as well. It is their "initial falsehood" that from the outset they expect or even impose all the properties of finite numbers upon the numbers in question, while on the other hand the infinite numbers, if they are to be considered in any form at all, must (in their contrast to the finite numbers) constitute an entirely new kind of number, whose nature is entirely dependent upon the nature of things and is an object of research, but not of our arbitrariness or prejudices. (Letter to Gustac Enestrom, quoted in Dauben p. 125)
Other objections depend on the idea that it is possible to define a function mapping every whole number on to some subset of whole numbers (though not one which captures every such subset). Cantor's theorem shows that at least one diagonal set is left over. We can then define a new function that does capture this diagonal set, and then define a further function that captures this set and so on ad infinitum. The problem with this argument is that there is be no set yielded by this "infinite" process, for that is what Cantor's theorem proves.
Hodges (1998 – get external link) has written an entertaining paper outlining other attempts. These include
- the claim that Cantor had chosen the wrong enumeration of the positive integers
- the argument that Cantor had used the wrong positive integers
- a denial that proof by contradiction is valid
For a list of anti-Cantor sites generally regarded as "cranky", see the external link below.
Objections to Cantor's Theorem
As shown above, most objections to Cantor's Theorem (i.e. the theorem that no set can be correlated one-one with all its subsets) result from misunderstanding it (for it relies on mostly logical assumptions and steps).
Wittgenstein, however, disparages it as trivial, a result that might have been well known before the invention of set theory, "and familiar even to school-children". The child wonders, given a list of decimals, how to write a number different from any on the list. "The method says: Not at all: change the first place of the first number, the second of the second one &c. &c., and you are sure of having written down a number that does not coincide with any of the given ones. This, Wittgenstein argues, changes the aspect of Cantor's discovery, which lies merely in the interpretation of this "familiar elementary calculation".
John Sowa ( a computer scientist) has made a similar observation that Cantor's discovery of the diagonal argument had occurred in a different context, it might have had a quite different impact.
I am not claiming to be a better mathematician than Cantor, but I am claiming to have the benefit of the work by Turing and others on noncomputability. If Turing's work had preceded Cantor's, I doubt that anyone would have considered [Cantor's argument] to be anything more than another variation of a noncomputability theorem. [reference?]
Objections to Hume's Principle
As argued above, many naïve objections depend on implicitly denying Hume's principle, and are therefore question-begging. Wittgenstein explicitly denies the principle, arguing that our concept of number depends essentially on counting. "Where the nonsense starts is with our habit of thinking of a large number as closer to infinity than a small one"
The expressions "divisible into two parts" and "divisible without limit" have completely different forms. This is, of course, the same case as the one in which someone operates with the word "infinite" as if it were a number word; because, in everyday speech, both are given as answers to the question 'How many?'(PR §173)
Does the relation m = 2n correlate the class of all numbers with one of its subclasses? No. It correlates any arbitrary number with another, and in that way we arrive at infinitely many pairs of classes, of which one is correlated with the other, but which are never related as class and subclass. Neither is this infinite process itself in some sense or other such a pair of classes. In the superstition that m = 2n correlates a class with its subclass, we merely have yet another case of ambiguous grammar. (PR §141).
He argues that the sign for a list of things is itself a list, and that a list is therefore inherently finite ("The symbol for a class is a list ... A cardinal number is an internal property of a list." (PR § 119)
Anti-Cantorians who propose that a "reality criterion" should be added to mathematics are also (in effect) denying that the concept of "number" truly applies to infinite sets. They argue [reference??] that we must take steps to guarantee that formal conclusions reached in the world of abstractions can be translated back into assertions about the concrete world. Now that we have a microscope for mathematics (i.e. the computer), it makes sense to think of the world of computation as real and concrete; infinite sets and power sets of infinite sets (and hence, real numbers etc.) exist only as useful fictions (abstractions) which help us reason about the concrete reality underlying mathematics; axioms and the rules of inference for abstractions should guarantee that any statement about the infinite should have implications for approximations to the infinite. Statements which have no implications observable in the world of computation, are fictions.
They [reference??] argue that it is not clear that anyone has produced a collection of axioms and rules of inference that satisfy these criteria, and are powerful enough to do all potentially useful mathematics. The constructivists have made progress towards that goal [reference??].
Others have argued that the mathematical logic that underpins set theory is essentially mathematical, and therefore lacks genuine logical underpinnings.
...classical logic was abstracted from the mathematics of finite sets and their subsets...Forgetful of this limited origin, one afterwards mistook that logic for something above and prior to all mathematics, and finally applied it, without justification, to the mathematics of infinite sets. This is the Fall and original sin of [Cantor's] set theory ..." (Weyl, 1946)
We cannot use the modern axiomatic method to establish the theory of sets. We cannot, in particular, simply employ the machinery of modern logic, modern mathematical logic, in establishing the theory of sets (Mayberry 2000, 7)
If God has mathematics of his own that needs to be done, let him do it himself." (Errett Bishop (19XX))
Others believe that the assumptions of set theory lead to conclusions that are unreal or absurd.
Set theory is based on polite lies, things we agree on even though we know they're not true. In some ways, the foundations of mathematics has an air of unreality. (William P. Thurston)
[The pure mathematicians] have followed a gleam that has led them out of this world... The fact that mathematics is valuable because it contributes to the understanding and mastery of of nature has been lost sight of... the work of the idealist who ignores reality will not survive." (Kline, 1982)
Philosopher Hartley Slater, in a number of papers, has repeatedly argued against the concept of "number" that underlies set theory (see external link below).
In reply, Cantoreans quote Cantor's saying (now inscribed on his tombstone) that "the essence of mathematics lies entirely in its freedom" (Grundlagen §8).
Mathematics is in its development entirely free and is only bound in the self-evident respect that its concepts must both be consistent with each other, and also stand in exact relationships, ordered by definitions, to those concepts which have previously been introduced and are already at hand and established. In particular, in the introduction of new numbers, it is only obligated to give definitions of them which will bestow such a determinacy and, in certain circumstances, such a relationship to the other numbers that they can in any given instance be precisely distinguished. As soon as a number satisfies all these conditions, it can and must be regarded in mathematics as existent and real. (ibid.)
Objection to the Axiom of infinity
One of the most common (and also the most respectable) objections to Cantor's theory of infinite number involves the axiom of infinity. It is generally recognised view by all logicians that this axiom is not a logical truth. Indeed, as Mark Sainsbury (1979, p.305) has argued "there is room for doubt about whether it is a contingent truth, since it is an open question whether the universe is finite or infinite". Bertrand Russell for many years tried to establish a foundation for mathematics that did not rely on this axiom. Mayberry (2000, p.10) has noted that "The set-theoretical axioms that sustain modern mathematics are self-evident in differing degrees. One of them – indeed, the most important of them, namely Cantor's axiom, the so-called axiom of infinity – has scarcely any claim to self-evidence at all, and it is one of my principle aims to investigate the possibility, and the consequences, of rejecting it".
This approach is known as finitism. Wittgenstein, whose viewpoint is essentially finitist, questioned the axiom and its corollaries in many places.
I have always said you can't speak of all numbers, because there's no such thing as 'all numbers'" (PR §129).
The endless path doesn’t have an end "infinitely far away", it has no end" (PR §123)
There's no such thing as "all numbers" simply because there are infinitely many." (PR §126)
The infinite number series is only the infinite possibility of finite series of numbers. It is senseless to speak of the whole infinite number series, as if it, too, were an extension." (PR §144)
Richard Arthur, philosopher and expert on Leibniz, has argued that Cantor's appeal to the idea of an actual infinite (formally captured by the axiom of infinity) is philosophically unjustified. Arthur argues that Leibniz' idea of a "syncategorematic" but actual infinity is philosophically more appealing. (See external link below for one of his papers).
The difficulty with finitism is to develop foundations of mathematics using finitist assumptions, that incorporates what everyone would reasonably regard as mathematics (for example, that includes real analysis).
Power Set
Wittgenstein also denies (in effect) the power set axiom. "Real numbers" are in fact rules, and are a different kind of thing entirely from cardinal numbers.
After all I have already said, it may sound trivial if I now say that the mistake in the set-theoretical approach consists time and again in treating laws and enumerations (lists) as essentially the same kind of thing and arranging them in parallel series so that one fills in gaps left by the other.(PG p. 461) My conception is: you can only put finite series alongside one another and in that way compare them; there's no point in putting dots after these finite stretches (as signs that the series goes on to infinity). Furthermore, you can compare a law with a law, but not a law with no law. (PR §181)
He compares a finite decimal expansion of pi to the bark of a tree. "What counts, or what something new can still grow from, is the inside of the trunk, where the tree's vital energy is. Altering the surface doesn’t change the tree at all. To change it, you have to penetrate the trunk which is still living ... it's as though the digits were dead excretions of the living essence of the root. Just as when in the course of its vital processes a snail discharges chalk, so building onto its shell."
Footnote
The quote "Later generations will regard set theory as a disease from which one has recovered" is from Kline[1982], and is apparently his translation of a quote from Poincare's speech "The future of mathematics" given in 1908. There has been considerable dispute about what Poincare actually intended to imply. Another translation reads "I think, [...] that it is important never to introduce any conception which may not be completely defined by a finite number of words. Whatever may be the remedy adopted, we can promise ourselves the joy of the physician called in to follow a beautiful pathological case." So Poincare's proposed cure for the disease, "never to introduce any conception which may not be completely defined by a finite number of words" would undermine Cantor's seminal idea underlying set theory; he was calling set theory a disease.
Wittgenstein (in a quotation that is frequently taken out of context)also compared set theory to a disease
If it were said: "Consideration of the diagonal procedure shews you that the concept "real number" has much less analogy with the concept "cardinal number" than we, being misled by certain analogies, inclined to believe", that would have a good and honest sense. But just the opposite happens: one pretends to compare the "set" of real numbers in magnitude with that of cardinal numbers. The difference in kind between the two conceptions is represented, by a skew form of expression, as difference of extension. I believe, and I hope, that a future generation will laugh at this hocus pocus.
The sickness of a time is cured by an alteration in the mode of life of human beings, and it was possible for the sickness of philosophical problems to get cured only through a changed mode of thought and of life, not through a medicine invented by an individual.
Think of the use of the motor-car producing or encouraging certain sicknesses, and mankind being plagued by such sickness until, from some cause or other, as the result of some development or other, it abandons the habit of driving. (RFM II.22-3)
External links
- "Cantor was wrong"
- Quotes from Cantor
- Original text of CAntor's argument with translation
- Philosopher and Leibniz scholar Richard Arthur's critique of Cantor's arguments for an actual infinity
References
Bishop, E. Introduction to Foundations of Constructive Analysis [date required]
- Frege, G. (1884) Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, transl. as The Foundations of Arithmetic, J.L. Austin, 2nd edition 1953.
- Dauben, G., Cantor.
- Hilbert, D., 1926. "Über das Unendliche". Mathematische Annalen, 95: 161—90. Translated as "On the infinite" in van Heijenoort, From Frege to Gödel: A source book in mathematical logic, 1879-1931, Harvard University Press.
- Hodges, W. "An Editor Recalls Some Hopeless Papers", The Bulletin of Symbolic Logic Volume 4, Number 1, March 1998.
- Kline, M., 1982. Mathematics: The Loss of Certainty. Oxford, ISBN 0195030850.
- Mayberry, J.P., The Foundations of Mathematics in the Theory of Sets, Encyclopedia of Mathematics and its Applications, Vol. 82, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 2000
- Poincare, H., 1908. "The Future of Mathematics". Address to the Fourth International Congress of Mathematicians . Published in Revue generale des Sciences pures et appliquees 23.
- Sainsbury, R.M., Russell, London 1979
- Weyl, H., 1946. "Mathematics and logic: A brief survey serving as a preface to a review of The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell". American Mathematical Monthly 53, pages 2—13.
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Grammar, translated by A.J.P. Kenny, Oxford, 1974
- Wittgenstein, L. Philosophical Remarks, translated by Hargreaves & White, Oxford, 1964
- Wittgenstein, L. Remarks on the Foundations of Mathematics, 3rd ed. Oxford 2001