Jump to content

User:Gro-Tsen/An ordinal collapsing function

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Gro-Tsen (talk | contribs) at 18:07, 14 March 2008 (re-edit examples and conditions for canonicalness (attempt to make them clearer)). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

This is an attempt to define and explicit a not-too-complicated ordinal collapsing function which should be useful for pedagogical purposes (to construct large countable ordinals). It presumably defines an ordinal notation up to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal, but I need to check this.

Definition

Let stand for the first uncountable ordinal, or, in fact, any ordinal which is (an -number and) guaranteed to be greater than all the countable ordinals which will be constructed (for example, the Church-Kleene ordinal is adequate for our purposes).

We define a function (which will be non-decreasing and continuous), taking an arbitrary ordinal to a countable ordinal , recursively on , as follows:

Assume has been defined for all , and we wish to define .
Let be the set of ordinals generated starting from , , and by recursively applying the following functions: ordinal addition, multiplication and exponentiation and the function , i.e., the restriction of to ordinals . (Formally, we define and inductively for all integers and we let be the union of the for all .)
Then is defined as the smallest ordinal not belonging to .

Computation of values of

Predicative start

First consider . It contains ordinals , , , , , , , , , , , , and so on. It also contains such ordinals as , , , . The first ordinal which it does not contain is (which is the limit of , , and so on — less than by assumption). The upper bound of the ordinals it contains is (the limit of , , and so on), but that is not so important. This shows that .

Similarly, contains the ordinals which can be formed from , , , and this time also , using addition, multiplication and exponentiation. This contains all the ordinals up to but not the latter, so . In this manner, we prove that inductively on : the proof works, however, only as long as . We therefore have:

for all , where is the smallest fixed point of .

(Here, the functions are the Veblen functions defined starting with .)

Now but is no larger, since cannot be constructed using finite applications of and thus never belongs to a set for , and the function remains “stuck” at for some time:

for all .

First impredicative values

Again, . However, when we come to computing , something has changed: since was (“artificially”) added to all the , we are permitted to take the value in the process. So contains all ordinals which can be built from , , , , the function up to and this time also itself, using addition, multiplication and exponentiation. The smallest ordinal not in is (the smallest -number after ).

We say that the definition and the next values of the function such as are impredicative because they use ordinals (here, ) greater than the ones which are being defined (here, ).

Values of up to the Feferman-Schütte ordinal

The fact that remains true for all (note, in particular, that : but since now the ordinal has been constructed there is nothing to prevent from going beyond this). However, at (the first fixed point of beyond ), the construction stops again, because cannot be constructed from smaller ordinals and by finitely applying the function. So we have .

The same reasoning shows that for all , where enumerates the fixed points of and is the first fixed point of . We then have .

Again, we can see that for some time: this remains true until the first fixed point of , which is the Feferman-Schütte ordinal. Thus, is the Feferman-Schütte ordinal.

Beyond the Feferman-Schütte ordinal

We have for all where is the next fixed point of . So, if enumerates the fixed points in question. (which can also be noted using the many-valued Veblen functions) we have , until the first fixed point of the itself, which will be . In this manner:

  • is the Ackermann ordinal (the range of the notation defined predicatively),
  • is the “small” Veblen ordinal (the range of the notations predicatively using finitely many variables),
  • is the “large” Veblen ordinal (the range of the notations predicatively using transfinitely-but-predicatively-many variables),
  • the limit of , , , etc., is the Bachmann-Howard ordinal: after this our function is constant, and we can go no further with the definition we have given.

Ordinal notations up to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal

We now explain how the function defines notations for ordinals up to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal.

A note about base representations

Recall that if is an ordinal which is a power of (for example itself, or , or ), any ordinal can be uniquely expressed in the form , where is a natural number, are non-zero ordinals less than , and are ordinal numbers (we allow ). This “base representation” is an obvious generalization of the Cantor normal form (which is the case ). Of course, it may quite well be that the expression is uninteresting, i.e., , but in any other case the must all be less than ; it may also be the case that the expression is trivial (i.e., , in which case and ).

If is an ordinal less than , then its base representation has coefficients (by definition) and exponents (because of the assumption ): hence one can rewrite these exponents in base and repeat the operation until the process terminates (any decreasing sequence of ordinals is finite). We call the resulting expression the iterated base representation of and the various coefficients involved (including as exponents) the pieces of the representation (they are all ), or, for short, the -pieces of .

Some properties of

  • The function is non-decreasing and continuous (this is more or less obvious from is definition).
  • If with then necessarily . Indeed, no ordinal with can belong to (otherwise its image by , which is would belong to — impossible); so is closed by everything under which is the closure, so they are equal.
  • Any value taken by is an -number (i.e., a fixed point of ). Indeed, if it were not, then by writing it in Cantor normal form, it could be expressed using sums, products and exponentiation from elements less than it, hence in , so it would be in , a contradiction.
  • Lemma: Assume is an -number and an ordinal such that for all : then the -pieces (defined above) of any element of are less than . Indeed, let be the set of ordinals all of whose -pieces are less than . Then is closed under addition, multiplication and exponentiation (because is an -number, so ordinals less than it are closed under addition, multiplication and exponentition). And also contains every for by assumption, and it contains , , , . So , which was to be shown.
  • Under the hypothesis of the previous lemma, (indeed, the lemma shows that ).
  • Any -number less than some element in the range of is itself in the range of (that is, omits no -number). Indeed: if is an -number not greater than the range of , let be the least upper bound of the such that : then by the above we have , but would contradict the fact that is the least upper bound — so .
  • Whenever , the set consists exactly of those ordinals (less than ) all of whose -pieces are less than . Indeed, we know that all ordinals less than , hence all ordinals (less than ) whose -pieces are less than , are in . Conversely, if we assume for all (in other words if is the least possible with ), the lemma gives the desired property. On the other hand, if for some , then we have already remarked and we can replace by the least possible with .

The ordinal notation

Using the facts above, we can define a (canonical) ordinal notation for every less than the Bachmann-Howard ordinal. We do this by induction on .

If is less than , we use the iterated Cantor normal form of . Otherwise, there exists a largest -number less or equal to (this is because the set of -numbers is closed): if then by induction we have defined a notation for and the base representation of gives one for , so we are finished.

It remains to deal with the case where is an -number: we have argued that, in this case, we can write for some (possibly uncountable) ordinal : let be the greatest possible such ordinal (which exists since is continuous). We use the iterated base representation of : it remains to show that every piece of this representation is less than (so we have already defined a notation for it). If this is not the case then, by the properties we have shown, does not contain ; but then (they are closed under the same operations, since the value of at can never be taken), so , contradicting the maximality of .

Examples

For ordinals less than , the canonical ordinal notation defined coincides with the iterated Cantor normal form (by definition).

For ordinals less than , the notation coincides with iterated base notation (the pieces being themselves written in iterated Cantor normal form): e.g., will be written , or, more accurately, . For ordinals less than , we similarly write in iterated base and then write the pieces in iterated base (and write the pieces of that in iterated Cantor normal form): so is written , or, more accurately, . Thus, up to , we always use the largest possible -number base which gives a non-trivial representation.

Beyond this, we may need to express ordinals beyond : this is always done in iterated -base, and the pieces themselves need to be expressed using the largest possible -number base which gives a non-trivial representation.

Conditions for canonicalness

The notations thus defined have the property that whenever they nest functions, the arguments of the “inner” function are always less than those of the “outer” one (this is a conseequence of the fact that the -pieces of , where is the largest possible such that for some -number , are all less than , as we have shown above). For example, does not occur as a notation: it is a well-defined expression (and it is equal to since is constant between and ), but it is not a notation produced by the inductive algorithm we have outlined.

Canonicalness can be checked recursively: an expression is canonical if and only if it is either the iterated Cantor normal form of an ordinal less than , or an iterated base representation all of whose pieces are canonical, for some where is itself written in iterated base representation all of whose pieces are canonical and less than . The order is checked by lexicographic verification at all levels (keeping in mind that is greater than any expression obtained by , and for canonical values the greater always trumps the lesser or even arbitrary sums, products and exponentials of the lesser).

For example, is a canonical notation for an ordinal which is less than the Feferman-Schütte ordinal: it can be written using the Veblen functions as .

Concerning the order, one might point out that (the Feferman-Schütte ordinal) is much more than (because is greater than of anything), and is itself much more than (because is greater than , so any sum-product-or-exponential expression involving and smaller value will remain less than ). In fact, is already less than .