Jump to content

User:Gro-Tsen/An ordinal collapsing function

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This is an old revision of this page, as edited by Gro-Tsen (talk | contribs) at 17:46, 10 March 2008 (Values up to the Feferman-Schütte ordinal). The present address (URL) is a permanent link to this revision, which may differ significantly from the current revision.

This is an attempt to define and explicit a not-too-complicated ordinal collapsing function which should be useful for pedagogical purposes (to construct large countable ordinals). It presumably defines an ordinal notation up to the Bachmann-Howard ordinal, but I need to check this.

Definition

Let stand for the first uncountable ordinal, or, in fact, any ordinal guaranteed to be greater than all the countable ordinals which will be constructed (for example, the Church-Kleene ordinal is adequate for our purposes).

We define a function (which will be non-decreasing), taking an arbitrary ordinal to a countable ordinal , recursively on , as follows:

Assume has been defined for all , and we wish to define .
Let be the set of ordinals generated starting from , , and by recursively applying the following functions: ordinal addition, multiplication and exponentiation and the function , i.e., the restriction of to ordinals . (Formally, we define and inductively for all integers and we let be the union of the for all .)
Then is defined as the smallest ordinal not belonging to .

Computation of values of

Predicative start

First consider . It contains ordinals , , , , , , , , , , , , and so on. It also contains such ordinals as , , , . The first ordinal which it does not contain is (which is the limit of , , and so on — less than by assumption). The upper bound of the ordinals it contains is (the limit of , , and so on), but that is not so important. This shows that .

Similarly, contains the ordinals which can be formed from , , , and this time also , using addition, multiplication and exponentiation. This contains all the ordinals up to but not the latter, so . In this manner, we prove that inductively on : the proof works, however, only as long as . We therefore have:

for all , where is the smallest fixed point of .

(Here, the functions are the Veblen functions defined starting with .)

Now but is no larger, since cannot be constructed using finite applications of and thus never belongs to a set for , and the function remains “stuck” at for some time:

for all .

First impredicative values

Again, . However, when we come to computing , something has changed: since was (“artificially”) added to all the , we are permitted to take the value in the process. So contains all ordinals which can be built from , , , , the function up to and this time also itself, using addition, multiplication and exponentiation. The smallest ordinal not in is (the smallest -number after ).

We say that the definition and the next values of the function such as are impredicative because they use ordinals (here, ) greater than the ones which are being defined (here, ).

Values of up to the Feferman-Schütte ordinal

The fact that remains true for all (note, in particular, that : but since now the ordinal has been constructed there is nothing to prevent from going beyond this). However, at (the first fixed point of beyond ), the construction stops again, because cannot be constructed from smaller ordinals and by finitely applying the function. So we have .

The same reasoning shows that for all , where enumerates the fixed points of an is the first fixed point of . We then have .

Again, we can see that for some time: this remains true until the first fixed point of , which is the Feferman-Schütte ordinal. Thus, is the Feferman-Schütte ordinal.