Utility representation theorem
In economics, a preference representation theorem is a theorem asserting that, under certain conditions, a preference ordering can be represented by a real-valued utility function, such that option A is preferred to option B if and only if the utility of A is larger than that of B.
Background
Suppose a person is asked questions of the form "Do you prefer A or B?" (when A and B can be options, actions to take, states of the world, consumption bundles, etc.). If the agent prefers A to B, we write . The set of all such preference-pairs forms the person's preference relation.
Instead of recording the person's preferences between every pair of options, it would be much more convenient to have a single utility function - a function u that assigns a real number to each option, such that if and only if .
Not every preference-relation has a utility-function representation. For example, if the relation is not transitive (the agent prefers A to B, B to C, and C to A), then it has no utility representation, since any such utility function would have to satisfy , which is impossible.
A utility representation theorem gives conditions on a preference relation, that are sufficient for the existence of a utility representation.
Often, one would like the representing function u to satisfy additional conditions, such as continuity. This requires additional conditions on the preference relation.
Definitions
The set of options is a topological space denoted by X. In some cases we assume that X is also a metric space; in particular, X can be a subset an Euclidean space Rm, such that each coordinate in {1,...,m} represents a commodity, and each m-vector in X represents a possible consumption bundle.
Preference relations
A preference relation is a subset of . It is denoted by either or :
- The notation is used when the relation is strict, that is, means that option A is strictly better than option B. In this case, the relation should be irreflexive, that is, does not hold. It should also be asymmetric, that is, implies that not .
- The notation is used when the relation is weak, that is, means that option A is at least as good as option B (A may be equivalent to B, or better than B). In this case, the relation should be reflexive, that is, always holds.
Given a weak preference relation , one can define its "strict part" and "indifference part" as follows:
- if and only if and not .
- if and only if and .
Given a strict preference relation , one can define its "weak part" and "indifference part" as follows:
- if and only if not ;
- if and only if not and not .
For every option , we define the contour sets at A:
- Given a weak preference relation , the weak upper contour set at A is the set of all options that are at least as good as A: . The weak lower contour set at A is is the set of all options that are at most as good as A: .
- Similarly, given a strict preference relation , the strict upper contour set at A is the set of all options better than A: , and the strict lower contour set at A is is the set of all options worse than A: .
Utility functions
A utility function is a function .
- A utility function u is said to represent a strict preference relation , if .
- A utility function u is said to represent a weak preference relation , if .
Complete preference relations
Debreu[1][2] proved the existence of a contiuous representation of a weak preference relation satisfying the following conditions:
- Transitive;
- Complete, that is, for every two options A, B in X, either or or both;
- For all , both the upper and the lower contour sets are topologically closed;
- The space X is second-countable. This means that there is a countable set S of open sets, such that every open set in X is the union of sets of the class S.[3] Second-countability is implied by the following properties (from weaker to stronger):
- The space X is separable and connected.
- There is a countable subset of X, , such that for every pair of non-equivalent elements , there is an element that separates them ().
- The set of equivalence classes of the indiffference relation is countable.
Incomplete preference relations
Incomplete preferences are partial order relations. This means that some options may be incomparable: it is possible that neither nor holds. Since real numbers are always comparable, it is impossible to have a representing function u with . There are several ways to cope with this issue.
See also
References
- ^ Debreu, Gerard (1954). Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function.
- ^ Debreu, Gerard (1986). "6. Representation of a preference ordering by a numerical function". Mathematical economics : twenty papers of Gerard Debreu ; introduction by Werner Hildenbrand (1st pbk. ed.). Cambridge [Cambridgeshire]: Cambridge University Press. ISBN 0-521-23736-X. OCLC 25466669.
- ^ Debreu, Gerard (1964). "Continuity properties of Paretian utility". International Economic Review. 5 (3): 285–293. doi:10.2307/2525513.
- ^ Richter, Marcel K. (1966). "Revealed Preference Theory". Econometrica. 34 (3): 635–645. doi:10.2307/1909773. ISSN 0012-9682.
- ^ Peleg, Bezalel (1970). "Utility Functions for Partially Ordered Topological Spaces". Econometrica. 38 (1): 93–96. doi:10.2307/1909243. ISSN 0012-9682.
- ^ Ok, Efe (2002). "Utility Representation of an Incomplete Preference Relation". Journal of Economic Theory. 104 (2): 429–449. ISSN 0022-0531.
- ^ Evren, Özgür; Ok, Efe A. (2011-08-01). "On the multi-utility representation of preference relations". Journal of Mathematical Economics. 47 (4): 554–563. doi:10.1016/j.jmateco.2011.07.003. ISSN 0304-4068.