In first-order arithmetic, the induction principles, bounding principles, and least number principles are three related families of first-order principles, which may or may not hold in nonstandard models of arithmetic. These principles are often used in reverse mathematics to calibrate the axiomatic strength of theorems.
Definitions
Informally, for a first-order formula of arithmetic
with one free variable, the induction principle for
expresses the validity of mathematical induction over
, while the least number principle for
asserts that if
has a witness, it has a least one. For a formula
in two free variables, the bounding principle for
states that, for a fixed bound
, if for every
there is
such that
, then we can find a bound on the
's.
Formally, the induction principle for
is the sentence:[1]
![{\displaystyle {\mathsf {I}}\varphi :\quad {\big [}\varphi (0)\land \forall x{\big (}\varphi (x)\to \varphi (x+1){\big )}{\big ]}\to \forall x\ \varphi (x)}](/media/api/rest_v1/media/math/render/svg/1b73ee04088b828dc1b60d75d98592c26e1196d3)
There is a similar strong induction principle for
:[1]
![{\displaystyle {\mathsf {I}}'\varphi :\quad \forall x{\big [}{\big (}\forall y<x\ \ \varphi (y){\big )}\to \varphi (x){\big ]}\to \forall x\ \varphi (x)}](/media/api/rest_v1/media/math/render/svg/c2fbecfb1fe723544c0dae387fc1d1091ebdd7c3)
The least number principle for
is the sentence:[1]

Finally, the bounding principle for
is the sentence:[1]
![{\displaystyle {\mathsf {B}}\psi :\quad \forall u{\big [}{\big (}\forall x<u\ \,\exists y\ \,\varphi (x,y){\big )}\to \exists v\ \,\forall x<u\ \,\exists y<v\ \,\varphi (x,y){\big ]}}](/media/api/rest_v1/media/math/render/svg/47c64a3e3270f9e71b86c998c85c5c527e26161a)
More commonly, we consider these principles not just for a single formula, but for a class of formulae in the arithmetical hierarchy. For example,
is the axiom schema consisting of
for every
formula
in one free variable.
Nonstandard models
It may seem that the principles
,
,
,
are trivial, and indeed, they hold for all formulae
,
in the standard model of arithmetic
. However, they become more relevant in nonstandard models. Recall that a nonstandard model of arithmetic has the form
for some linear order
. In other words, it consists of an initial copy of
, whose elements are called finite or standard, followed by many copies of
arranged in the shape of
, whose elements are called infinite or nonstandard.
Now, considering the principles
,
,
,
in a nonstandard model
, we can see how they might fail. For example, the hypothesis of the induction principle
only ensures that
holds for all elements in the standard part of
- it may not hold for the nonstandard elements, who can't be reached by iterating the successor operation from zero. Similarly, the bounding principle
might fail if the bound
is nonstandard, as then the (infinite) collection of
could be cofinal in
.
Relations between the principles
The following relations hold between the principles:[1]
for every formula
;
;
, and both implications are strict;
;
, but it is not known if this reverses.
Over the weak base theory
, Slaman proved that
.[2]
Reverse mathematics
The induction, bounding and least number principles are commonly used in reverse mathematics and second-order arithmetic. For example,
is part of the definition of the subsystem
of second-order arithmetic. Hence,
,
and
are all theorems of
. The subsystem
proves all the principles
,
,
,
for arithmetical
,
. The infinite pigeonhole principle is known to be equivalent to
and
over
.[3]
References